The moral of the story: an introduction to ethics nina rosenstand - Download the ebook now and read
The Moral of the Story: An Introduction to Ethics Nina Rosenstand
Visit to download the full and correct content document: https://textbookfull.com/product/the-moral-of-the-story-an-introduction-to-ethics-nina-r osenstand/
More products digital (pdf, epub, mobi) instant download maybe you interests ...
LC record available at https://lccn.loc.gov/2016048988
The Internet addresses listed in the text were accurate at the time of publication. The inclusion of a website does not indicate an endorsement by the authors or McGraw-Hill Education, and McGraw-Hill Education does not guarantee the accuracy of the information presented at these sites.
mheducation.com/highered
For Craig and my parents
Immorality may be fun, but it isn’t fun enough to take the place of 100 percent virtue and three square meals a day.
Design for Living
Preface ix Acknowledgments xvi
PART 1
The Story as a Tool of Ethics
Chapter 1
Thinking About Values 1
Living in Interesting Times 1
Values, Morals, and Ethics 5
Good and Evil 9
Debating Moral Issues from Religion to Neurobiology and Storytelling 17
Virtue Ethics and Authenticity: Contemporary Perspectives 470
Ethics and the Morality of Virtue as Political Concepts 470
Have Virtue, and Then Go Ahead: Mayo, Foot, and Sommers 473
The Quest for Authenticity: Kierkegaard, Nietzsche, Heidegger, Sartre, and Levinas 483
primary reading: Søren Kierkegaard, Johannes Climacus 513
primary reading: Søren Kierkegaard, Either/Or 514
primary reading: Jean-Paul Sartre, Existentialism Is a Humanism 514
primary reading: Dwight Furrow, A Culture of Care 517
narrative: Groundhog Day 521
narrative: No Exit 523
narrative: Good Will Hunting 524
narrative: The Searchers 528
Chapter 11
Case Studies in Virtue 533
Courage of the Physical and Moral Kind 533
Compassion: From Hume to Huck Finn 540
Gratitude: Asian Tradition and Western Modernity 551
Virtue and Conduct: The Option of Soft Universalism 566
Diversity, Politics, and Common Ground? 570
primary reading: John McCain, Why Courage Matters: The Way to a Braver Life 572
primary reading: Philip Hallie, Tales of Good and Evil, Help and Harm 575
primary reading: Jesse Prinz, Is Empathy Necessary for Morality? 577
narrative: Courage: Band of Brothers, Third Episode, “Carentan” 580
narrative: Courage: True Grit 582
narrative: Courage: Cowardice 585
narrative: Compassion: The Parable of the Good Samaritan 589
narrative: Compassion: Schindler’s List 590
narrative: Gratitude: Pay It Forward 593
Chapter 12
Different Gender, Different Ethics? 597
Feminism and Virtue Theory 597
What Is Gender Equality? 598
Women’s Historical Role in the Public Sphere 602
The Rise of Modern Feminism 609
Classical, Difference, and Radical Feminism 615
primary reading: Harriet Taylor Mill, Enfranchisement of Women 632
narrative: A Doll’s House 635
narrative: Maids of Misfortune 640
narrative: A Thousand Splendid Suns 644
Chapter 13 Applied Ethics: A Sampler 648
The Question of Abortion and Personhood 648
Euthanasia as a Right to Choose? 651
Media Ethics and Media Bias 654
Business Ethics: The Rules of the Game 664
Just War Theory 673
Animal Welfare and Animal Rights 681
Ethics of the Environment: Think Globally, Act Locally 687
The Death Penalty 694
The Ethics of Self-Improvement: Narrative Identity 703
A Final Word 712
primary reading: Amber Levanon Seligson and Laurie Choi, Critical Elements of an Organizational Ethical Culture 713
primary reading: FDA U.S. Food and Drug Administration, Background on the FDA Food Safety Modernization Act (FSMA) 714
primary reading: Great Ape Project, The Declaration on Great Apes 718
primary reading: Marc Bekoff and Jessica Pierce, Wild Justice 719
primary reading: Rachel Gandy, July 2, 2015, Prison Policy Initiative, Justice Breyer Argues the Death Penalty Isn’t Just Cruel, It’s Unusual Too 723
narrative: Media Ethics: Spotlight 726
narrative: Business Ethics: The Insider 728
narrative: The Death Penalty: The Jigsaw Man 731
narrative: The Death Penalty: The Life of David Gale 733
narrative: Telling One’s Own Story: True Detective Season 1 736
Bibliography 740
Glossary 750 Index 757
Preface
Like the previous editions of The Moral of the Story, the eighth edition is a combination of classical questions in ethical theory and contemporary issues. The general concept remains the same: that discussions about moral issues can be facilitated using stories as examples, as a form of ethics lab where solutions can be tried out under controlled conditions. The book is written primarily for such college courses as Introduction to Ethics; Moral Philosophy; and Introduction to Philosophy: Values. Many textbooks in value theory or ethics choose to focus on problems of social importance, such as abortion, euthanasia, and capital punishment. This book reflects my own teaching experience that it is better for students to be introduced to basic ethical theory before they are plunged into discussions involving moral judgments. Consequently, The Moral of the Story provides an overview of influential classical and contemporary approaches to ethical theory. However, without practical application of the theories, there can be no complete understanding of the problems raised, so each chapter includes examples that illustrate and explore the issues. As in previous editions, each chapter concludes with a section of examples—summaries and excerpts—taken from the world of fiction, novels and films in particular.
Within the last few decades, narrative theory has carved out a niche in American and European philosophy as well as in other academic disciplines. It is no longer unusual for ethicists and other thinkers to include works of fiction in their courses as well as in their professional papers, not only as examples of problem solving, but also as illustrations of an epistemological phenomenon: Humans are, in Alasdair MacIntyre’s words, storytelling animals, and we humans seem to choose the narrative form as our favorite way to structure meaning as we attempt to make sense of our reality. The narrative trend is making itself felt in other fields as well: The medical profession is looking to stories that teach about doctor-patient relationships; psychotherapists recommend that patients watch films to achieve an understanding of their own situation, and have patients write stories with themselves as the lead character. The court system is making use of films and novels to reach young people in trouble with the law. The U.S. military is partnering up with authors to anticipate possible scenarios for future assaults on American interests. NASA is teaming up with science fiction writers and Hollywood in an attempt to once again make space exploration exciting for new generations of readers, and judging from the success of recent films, that approach is working. And neuroscientists tell us that we understand the world by superimposing narrative order on the chaos we experience. It seems that new fields are constantly being added to the list of professions that are discovering, or rediscovering, the potential of stories.
Organization
Like the previous editions, the eighth edition of The Moral of the Story is divided into three major sections. Part 1 introduces the topic of ethics and places the phenomenon of storytelling within the context of moral education and discussion. Part 2 examines the conduct theories of ethical relativism, psychological and ethical egoism, altruism, utilitarianism, and Kantian deontology, and explores the concepts of personhood, rights, and justice. Part 3 focuses on the subject of virtue theory and contains chapters on Socrates and Plato, Aristotle, contemporary virtue theories in America, theories of authenticity in the Continental tradition, and gender theory. The virtues of courage, compassion, and gratitude are examined in detail, and the book concludes with a more detailed discussion of a broad selection of moral issues, applying theories introduced in previous chapters. Each chapter concludes with a set of study questions, a section of Primary Readings with excerpts from classical and contemporary texts, and a section of Narratives, a collection of stories that illustrate the moral issues raised in the chapter. The Primary Readings are selected for their value as discussion topics; they don’t necessarily reflect my own views, and I have made no attempt to select readings that cover all possible angles, because of space limitations. The Narratives will be described in more detail below.
Major Changes to the Eighth Edition
Throughout the eighth edition all examples and discussions reflecting moral and social issues in the news have been updated wherever an update seemed reasonable. In addition, key words and names have been either italicized or changed to bold type for an easy overview, all depending on the context. Major changes to the eighth edition include the following: as with every new edition, Chapter One has been thoroughly revised, with a new introduction, reflecting the turbulent times we live in. Stephen Pinker’s famous theory of times getting better is juxtaposed with John Gray’s more pessimistic vision. The section “Good and Evil” has been updated and expanded to examine current stories of egregiously evil behavior. Finally, the Narratives section now includes a summary and excerpt of the famous short story “The Lottery.”
Chapter Two has been updated with current examples of films and television shows illustrating moral problems, including Fargo and True Detective. New boxes feature the Zombie phenomenon in entertainment, virtual reality and narrative video games, and the moral complexities of the book/HBO series Game of Thrones
Chapter Three has an updated discussion of the female genital mutilation issue, and updates of other current issues.
Chapter Four expands upon the concept of “heroes” to explore the actions of individuals giving up their lives to save students and co-workers in mass shootings and acts of terrorism. In addition, the Narratives section now includes the Swedish film Force Majeure which starts out as a family film and spirals downward into a study of fundamental selfishness.
Chapter Five has a new box on the concept of “consequences,” and another on the movie The Purge and its take on the hedonistic calculus. In the Narratives
section, the film Outbreak has been reinstated from previous editions due to the relevancy of its subject matter, and the recent film Contagion has been added as a companion story.
Chapter Six has an expanded section on animal cognition, and the Narratives section now includes the graphic novel (and film) Watchmen
Chapter Seven has been thoroughly updated with discussions about cloning and personhood, a reference to the recent shootings, both by and of police officers, a new box exploring the moral implications of creating robots, and an update on new views on restorative justice. The Narratives section has had the classic science fiction film Blade Runner reinstated, and the new film Ex Machina has been added as a companion piece.
Chapter Eight has a new box on American/Canadian Indian values successfully promoted by an imposter, Archie Grey Owl.
Chapter Nine has a new section on Intelligent Design, as well as the complete list of Aristotle’s original virtues and vices.
Chapter Ten has a new box dedicated to a brief discussion of hard determinism, free will, and compatibilism. In addition, the Levinas section has been expanded with a discussion of the European refugee crisis seen from the point of view of Levinas’s theory of the Other.
Chapter Eleven has been updated with new examples of courageous behavior, related to terror attacks and school shootings. The classic Japanese novel Kokoro has been added to the Narratives section.
Chapter Twelve has an update on gender-neutral language, as well as an update on the changes in military policies allowing women in combat. In addition, the story of Hypatia has been added, and the boxes on conservative feminism, the princess phenomenon, as well as same-sex marriage have been updated.
Chapter Thirteen has several thoroughly revised sections, including new perspectives on euthanasia, and updates on media ethics issues. A new box in the Business Ethics section explores the origin of the 2008 financial crisis seen through the film The Big Short, and another new box discusses the phenomenon of personal branding. The section on Just War has a new box focusing on the war in Iraq. The section on Environmental Ethics has been updated and the Death Penalty section has been revised with new examples and data. In the section on Telling One’s Life as a Story, a box from the previous edition’s Chapter Ten on personal identity has found a better home. The Primary Readings now include an excerpt from the U.S. Food and Drug Administration’s presentation of the FSMA (FDA Food Safety Modernization Act) from 2011, an excerpt from Marc Bekoff and Jessica Pierce’s Wild Justice, and a column by Rachel Gandy on Justice Breyer’s opinion on the death penalty. New narratives include the Academy Award–winning film Spotlight and the acclaimed HBO series True Detective, Season 1.
I would like to mention an issue that I myself am not too happy about: the field of textbook publishing is changing, and some changes have impacted this 8th edition of The Moral of the Story. Those readers who have used this book through several editions will notice some changes in the Primary Readings and Narratives sections: Some texts have disappeared, or have been replaced with public-domain translations,
paraphrased summaries and short excerpts. This decision was necessary, due to the fact that permissions to include lengthy text excerpts in textbooks have become much harder or downright impossible to obtain, and I had no choice but to exclude some texts despite them being a staple in the book for many editions. In addition, I’ve had to abandon the inclusion of several new, planned primary readings, such as an excerpt from Mary Midgley’s “Mythology of Selfishness.” As a compromise I have chosen to maintain the presence of such texts in the book by placing detailed descriptions and short excerpts into the chapter text itself, or in the case of narratives (particularly the novels), paraphrasing the stories and keeping brief excerpts of an essential paragraph or two allowed under the public domain notion. I hope I have done those texts justice.
Using the Narratives
The Narratives have been chosen from a wide variety of sources ranging from epic prose, poems, and novels to films, and one graphic novel. I wish to emphasize that from a literary and artistic point of view, summaries and excerpts do not do the originals justice; a story worth experiencing, be it a novel, short story, or film, can’t be reduced to a mere plot outline or fragment and still retain all of its essence. As Martha Nussbaum says, the form is an inherent part of the story content. Usually, there is more to the story than the bare bones of a moral problem, and in writing these summaries I have had to disregard much of the richness of story and character development. Nevertheless, I have chosen the summary or excerpt format in order to discuss a number of different stories and genres as they relate to specific issues in ethics. Because I believe it is important to show that there is a cross-cultural, historic tradition of exploring moral problems through telling a story, I have opted for a broad selection of Narratives. Each chapter has several Narratives, and some additional narratives— or narratives from previous editions—now appear in boxes within the chapter text, but it is not my intention that the instructor should feel obligated to cover all of them in one course; rather, they should be regarded as options that can be alternated from semester to semester—a method I like to use myself for the sake of variety. There are, of course, other ways than summaries in which stories and ethical theory can be brought together; one might, for instance, select one or two short stories or films in their original format for class discussion, or make them available to the students for extra credit. I hope that instructors will indeed select a few stories—novels, short stories, or films—for their classes to experience firsthand. However, the Narratives are written so that firsthand experience should not be necessary to a discussion of the problem presented by the story. The summaries and excerpts give readers just enough information to enable them to discuss the moral problem presented. I hope that some readers will become inspired to seek out the originals on their own. In most cases the ending is important to the moral significance of a story, and whenever that is the case, I include that ending. In cases where the ending is not significant to the moral drama, I have done my best to avoid giving it away because I don’t want to be a spoiler. Because space is limited, I have not been able to include more than a sampling of stories, and I readily admit that my choices are subjective ones; I personally find
them interesting as illustrations and effective in a classroom context where students come from many different cultural backgrounds. Because I am a naturalized U.S. citizen, originally a native of Denmark, I have chosen to include a few references to the Scandinavian literary and film tradition. I am fully aware that others might choose other stories or even choose different ethical problems to illustrate, and I am grateful to the many users of the previous seven editions, instructors as well as students, who have let me know about their favorite stories and how they thought this selection of stories might be expanded and improved. The new Narratives reflect some of those suggestions.
Some students (and instructors) may be disappointed that this edition has no narratives from video games. I hear from students and colleagues that video games are increasingly focused on elaborate narratives rather than merely accumulating points and killing enemy entities, and I know from colleagues that some narrative video games now offer interesting ways of experiencing moral problems and decision-making, even involving scenarios of emotional and ethical complexity. However, since I have no experience with actually playing such games (my video gaming experience ended some time in the 1990s), I have not included any games in the Narratives sections.
As was the case with previous revisions, I have had to make some difficult choices: To keep the cost of the book down, I have had to cut materials from previous editions to make room for new readings, updates, and narratives. This is never easy, because many of the older readings and stories are favorites of mine, and I am well aware that they may also be the favorites of instructors using this book, and important elements in well-functioning syllabi. Fortunately, in this electronic age we can include new materials without losing all of the older elements. The Connect site (see description below) will include a number of narratives from previous editions, such as The Invention of Lying, Eat Drink Man Woman, Return to Paradise, Match Point, Dead Man Walking, Do the Right Thing, and Thelma and Louise for easy access and downloading by instructors. As in previous editions, I emphasize that I wholeheartedly welcome e-mails from students as well as instructors who use this book, with relevant comments and suggestions for new stories as well as additional philosophical perspectives: nrosenst@sdccd.edu.
The Eighth edition of The Moral of the Story, is now available online with Connect, McGraw-Hill Education’s integrated assignment and assessment platform. Connect also offers SmartBook for the new edition, which is the first adaptive reading experience proven to improve grades and help students study more effectively. All of the title’s website and ancillary content is also available through Connect, including:
• A full Test Bank of multiple-choice questions that test students on central concepts and ideas in each chapter.
• An Instructor’s Manual for each chapter with full chapter outlines, sample test questions, and discussion topics.
McGraw-Hill Connect®
Learn Without Limits
Connect is a teaching and learning platform that is proven to deliver better results for students and instructors.
Connect empowers students by continually adapting to deliver precisely what they need, when they need it, and how they need it, so your class time is more engaging and effective.
73% of instructors who use Connect require it; instructor satisfaction increases by 28% when Connect is required.
Analytics
Connect Insight®
Connect Insight is Connect’s new one-of-a-kind visual analytics dashboard—now available for both instructors and students—that provides at-a-glance information regarding student performance, which is immediately actionable. By presenting assignment, assessment, and topical performance results together with a time metric that is easily visible for aggregate or individual results, Connect Insight gives the user the ability to take a just-in-time approach to teaching and learning, which was never before available. Connect Insight presents data that empowers students and helps instructors improve class performance in a way that is efficient and effective.
Mobile
Connect’s new, intuitive mobile interface gives students and instructors flexible and convenient, anytime–anywhere access to all components of the Connect platform.
Using Connect improves retention rates by 19.8%, passing rates by 12.7%, and exam scores by 9.1%.
Students can view their results for any Connect course.
Adaptive
More students earn A’s and B’s when they use McGraw-Hill Education Adaptive products.
SmartBook®
Proven to help students improve grades and study more efficiently, SmartBook contains the same content within the print book, but actively tailors that content to the needs of the individual. SmartBook’s adaptive technology provides precise, personalized instruction on what the student should do next, guiding the student to master and remember key concepts, targeting gaps in knowledge and offering customized feedback, and driving the student toward comprehension and retention of the subject matter. Available on tablets, SmartBook puts learning at the student’s fingertips—anywhere, anytime.
Over 8 billion questions have been answered, making McGraw-Hill Education products more intelligent, reliable, and precise.
www.mheducation.com
T HE ADAPTIVE READING EXPERIENCE DESIGNED TO TRANSFORM THE WAY STUDENTS READ
Acknowledgments
As always, I first want to thank my students in the classes Introduction to Philosophy: Values, Philosophy of Women, Issues in Social Philosophy, Reflections on Human Nature, Human Nature and Society, and Philosophy and Literature for their enthusiastic cooperation in suggesting good stories and discussing drafts of the stories and study questions with me—an invaluable help in fine-tuning the summaries and questions.
Next, I would like to thank the Project Team at McGraw-Hill Higher Education for good communication and support, in particular Development Editor Erin Guendelsberger for her prompt e-mails and great suggestions. Thanks also to: Brand Managers Jamie Laferrera and Penina Braffman, Content Project Manager Melissa Leick, Marketing Manager Meredith Leo, Content Licensing Specialist Shannon Manderschied, Photo Researcher Stacey Dong Miskell, and Project Manager for MPS Ldt. Touseen Qadri. The cover painting is by artist Karen Barbour, and I am delighted that her evocative visions have represented The Moral of the Story through eight editions. I also wish to thank the following reviewers, and one anonymous reviewer, for their suggestions:
Joy Branch, Southern Union State Community College
Lynn G Bartholome, Monroe Community College
Mary Ann Sellars, Ivy Tech Community College, Southwest Irene Byrnes, SUNY Broome Community College
My colleagues at the Social Sciences and Behavioral and Multicultural Studies Department at San Diego Mesa College, which includes professors, adjuncts, and professors emeritus/emerita of philosophy, history, political science, and geography, are a wonderful support group—many of us come from different professional fields and have different outlooks on many things, but we all cherish the ambience of professional integrity in our workplace and find time to discuss ethics-related issues on a regular basis: Thank you to my colleagues from the Social Sciences Department as well as other departments: In particular I wish to thank Department Chair John Crocitti, Jonathan McLeod, Donald Abbott, Dwight Furrow, and Dean Charles Zappia. In addition, I would like to express my appreciation to J. Craig Bradley, Stephen Pacheco, and Josef Binter for sharing their research with me, and to Tony Pettina for being an advance reader on the section on Asian moral philosophy.
I would like to thank Ian Duckles for his invaluable help in steering me through the maze of narrative open-ended video games with a moral aspect, and I am looking forward to future conversations with him as well as Mary Gwin with whom I share a fascination for the potential of stories as moral laboratories, and an interest in the life quality of companion animals.
At Mesa College we have a biannual Meeting of the Minds tradition where philosophy faculty, contract as well as adjuncts, meet and share our thoughts about teaching and engage in debates about classical and current philosophical topics. I want to express my appreciation for the professional enthusiasm of all the philosophy faculty who participate regularly in these meetings. My colleague John Berteaux, philosophy professor at Monterey State University, deserves my heartfelt thanks for being an old friend and colleague from the adjunct days who shares my concerns for issues in social ethics and who has generously shared his work, including his archive of newspaper columns with me. A special word of appreciation goes to my friend and colleague Harold Weiss, professor of philosophy at Northhampton Community College who has been enormously helpful in suggesting new material for the eighth edition, including several films I would otherwise not have thought of including. A profound note of appreciation goes to my colleague and friend Melinda Campbell, professor of philosophy at National University, San Diego, for her helpful comments to the seventh edition and support for the updates in the eighth edition, as well as sharing her insight into using The Moral of the Story for her online courses. And I would like to say a special thank you to my friend and former colleague, Professor Emerita of history Mary Lou Locke. I am grateful for her permission, as author M. Louisa Locke, to include an excerpt from her first novel in Chapter 12. I would also like to thank Reiko Abe Auestad, Oslo University, Norway, for her interest in this book, and her suggestion to bring the novel Koroko into the new edition, my good friend Steve Fischer for sharing his insight into the phenomenon of personal branding, and my good friend Randi McKenzie for her support and wise suggestions.
Because this edition builds upon the previous seven editions, I would like to acknowledge the generous support and suggestions I have received in the past from a very large number of people—friends, colleagues, and professionals from a wide variety of fields—who have graciously given me their time and assistance. Your input has been invaluable to me, and I am profoundly grateful to you all.
My father, Finn Rosenstand, raconteur par excellence, passed away the day after Christmas 2014, four weeks shy of his 100th birthday. He was alert and lucid until his final day and lived his life according to his motto, maeden agan, ancient Greek for “everything in moderation.” He frequently mentioned that if given the choice, he would like to live every single day all over again—something that Nietzsche would have appreciated as a sign that one truly loves life and is not a nay-sayer. Throughout my career as a philosophy instructor, and writer of textbooks and other works, he tirelessly looked for material I might be able to use; all seven previous editions have benefited from his research and suggestions. Throughout my childhood and young adulthood my father used to read aloud to my mother and me from the treasures of
Danish and world literature in the long, dark, Scandinavian fall and winter evenings. As I have mentioned in previous editions, he was instrumental in opening my mind to intellectual curiosity, human compassion, and a passion for history, literature, and film. My appreciation for what he has meant to me has no boundaries.
But most of all, I want to thank my husband, Craig R. Covner, for his strength and loving support, for always being ready to share his insight into American history as well as Hollywood film history, for his understanding and patience with me in my writer’s work-mode, and for his wonderful sense of humor.
Chapter One Thinking About Values
Living in Interesting Times
Sometimes we hear about an old Chinese saying, May you live in interesting times, and, according to tradition, it is meant as a curse, not a benign wish. As a matter of fact, there doesn’t seem to actually be such an ancient Chinese expression; the one that comes closest seems to be 1600 century Chinese writer Feng Menlong’s opinion that it is “Better to be a dog in a peaceful time than a human in a chaotic world,” and the “interesting times” expression seems to have been introduced by Western writers in the 1930s. But whether or not it really is an ancient Chinese curse, or an idea concocted by sarcastic Westerners and attributed to Chinese wisdom, it strikes a chord in many hearts these days. As much as we in the Western modern world have been used to thinking that an exciting life is a good life, there is an ancient cross-cultural wisdom present in the saying, echoed in famous French seventeenth century philosopher René Descartes’s personal motto, Bene vixit qui bene latuit, “One lives well who hides well”: a quiet life, safe from turmoil and violent death, has been the dream of many a human being who has fled destruction and persecution, or kept a low profile hoping that the tide of violence might pass them by. And here we are, in our various cities and regions of the West and around the world, living two kinds of lives these days, our normal lives with their normal hopes for our families, our health and our jobs, and a New Normal life where we are constantly reminded that we are vulnerable, to a degree that few of us had imagined only a few decades ago. At the global level we are experiencing climate turmoil that questions our previous models of predictability (in Chapter 13 you can read more about the debate over climate change); in addition, people from some parts of the world are on the move, changing demographics and economies in the places they migrate to, on a scale not seen since before World War II. Some flee their war- and terror-ridden countries. Others seek a better life, financially, for themselves and their families, and yet others, it would seem, are set on bringing their brand of terror with them to new venues. And locally, terror massacres and school shootings are reminders that “hiding well” is no guarantee that sudden disaster will pass you by. All this unpredictability takes its toll; even people from cultures that have previously registered high on the “happiness” scale are registering lower than before. We are worried about tomorrow, overall. Some people predict that we in the next half-century may be facing challenges, environmental as well as financial and political, never seen before in recorded human history.
And yet: Human beings are amazingly resilient. Humans have been through plagues, famine, natural disasters, and wholesale abuse by fellow human beings. In other words, we have always lived in “interesting times.” And perhaps our current era is actually even less “interesting” than earlier centuries. As American-Canadian cognitive scientist and linguist Steven Pinker stresses, statistically we live in far less violent times now than for instance the Middle Ages. In The Better Angles of Our Nature (2011) Pinker says,
“We now know that native peoples, whose lives are so romanticized in today’s children’s books, had rates of death from warfare that were greater than those of our world wars. The romantic visions of medieval Europe omit the exquisitely crafted instruments of torture and are innocent of the thirtyfold greater risk of murder in those times. The centuries for which people are nostalgic were times in which the wife of an adulterer could have her nose cut off, children as young as eight could be hanged for property crimes, a prisoner’s family could be charged for easement of irons, a witch could be sawn in half, and a sailor could be flogged to a pulp. The moral commonplaces of our age, such as that slavery, war, and torture are wrong, would have been seen as saccharine sentimentality, and our notion of universal human rights almost incoherent. The forces of modernity—reason, science, humanism, individual rights—have not, of course, pushed steadily in one direction; nor will they ever bring about a utopia or end the frictions and hurts that come with being human. But on top of all the benefits that modernity has brought us in health, experience, and knowledge, we can add its role in the reduction of violence.”
So are we moving toward a kinder, gentler, more peaceful world, because we, as Pinker thinks, are paying more attention to the voice of reason and common sense? An opposing view has been voiced by British political philosopher John Gray who finds Pinker’s optimism naive. For Gray, civilization is a fragile entity. In “Steven Pinker is wrong about violence and war” Gray says, “Improvements in civilization are real enough, but they come and go. While knowledge and invention may grow cumulatively and at an accelerating rate, advances in ethics and politics are erratic, discontinuous and easily lost. Amid the general drift, cycles can be discerned: peace and freedom alternate with war and tyranny, eras of increasing wealth with periods of economic collapse. Instead of becoming ever stronger and more widely spread, civilization remains inherently fragile and regularly succumbs to barbarism.” So who is right? Are we teetering on the brink of some kind of cultural collapse, or are we just in medias res (in the middle of things), looking at chaotic life from the inside, unable to see the bigger and fairly reassuring picture?
As I frequently mention to my students, and I will pass it on to you, the reader, the future envisioned in overall positive terms by Pinker and in negative terms by Gray is, in many ways, in your hands. You may not have the actual power to mold the future, but you will have the power to help inspire and even mold reactions of fellow human beings to whatever challenges are waiting for us, up ahead in the stream of time, through social media, and whatever other kind of media we may have in the future. Being forearmed with knowledge, not only of the past, but with
the values of both past and present, will help you in your decision-making. And so we embark on this journey into The Moral of the Story, examining moral value systems of primarily the Western culture in contemporary and modern times as well as past centuries—because each new idea is generally a reaction to older ideas that have somehow become inadequate. The book, however, is not a chronological journey. It moves through modern moral problems, to equivalents in the past, and back to contemporary scenarios.
The fact is that we all encounter issues involving moral values on an everyday basis; sometimes they involve small decisions, sometimes large ones. Some everyday issues that are in the news are questions about Internet file sharing /copying/ downloading of copyrighted material. Some find it is rightfully illegal, while others find it to be completely acceptable and even a morally decent thing—sharing new ideas with others. Another issue that you may have been engaged in discussing is the ethics of texting and Facebook communication, and what exactly is an appropriate level of intimacy and sharing of information if it risks getting into the wrong hands? And what is the kind of information we can, in all decency, text to each other—Is it acceptable to break up through a text message? Sext—send sexy pictures taken with or without the portrayed person’s permission? Share gossip? All these questions involve an underlying code of ethics. So, too, do the major moral issues we as a society are struggling with: Some of the big questions and even conflicts we have dealt with during the first decade of this century have involved the right to marry whomever you choose, including a person of your own gender; the question of the appropriate response to terrorism (through the civil courts, or military actions and tribunals); the use of torture in interrogations of presumed terrorists; the right to have access to euthanasia; the continued question about the moral status of abortion (both of these topics are featured in Chapter 13); the periodically resurfacing discussion about the right to gun ownership; the moral status of pets as property or family members; and other such issues that involve both moral and legal perspectives. This book will deal with some of those issues, but perhaps more important, it will deal with the values underlying those issues—the moral theories explaining those values. Later in this chapter we look at the terms of values, morals, and ethics. Some questions involving values focus on how we ought to behave vis-à-vis other human beings; any moral theory that involves a focus on action, on what to do, is known as an ethic of conduct, and we will look at various theories of ethics of conduct from Chapter 3 through Chapter 7. However, there is a different kind of moral philosophy that focuses on developing a good character, on how to be, generally referred to as virtue ethics, and that is our topic for Chapters 8 through 11. Of the remaining chapters, this chapter and Chapter 2 explore the current spectrum of moral discussions and the influence of storytelling as a tool for both teaching and learning about moral values. Chapter 12 looks at various models of ethics as seen by feminists, and Chapter 13 represents what is known as “applied ethics,” moral philosophies applied to specific cases or scenarios, such as the abortion issue, euthanasia, media ethics, just-war theory, animal rights, and environmental ethics. For each of the issues mentioned above there is generally a side promoting it and a side arguing against it. We’re used to that kind of debate in a free society,
and you’ll see some of those questions discussed in this book, in particular in Chapters 7 and 13. What we have also become used to during the past decades is that our nation seems more divided than in previous decades—what some political commentators have labeled a “50-50 nation.” In election years, particularly in the first decade of the twenty-first century, political opinions divided the country almost in half—at least if there were only two options to choose from, Democratic or Republican. The presidential elections of 2000 and 2016 were particularly close. In 2016 the Republican candidate Donald Trump the clear winner of the electoral votes, while the Democratic candidate Hillary Clinton won the popular vote. Even if we have “blue states” and “red states” showing up on the electoral map, there are blue and red areas within each state. This is of course politics, and our main topic is going to be ethics and values, but there is a relevant connection: There is a set of moral values commonly associated with Democratic policies, such as being pro-choice/pro-abortion, increased gun control, pro-gay rights, and scaling back military operations, and another associated with Republican politics generally advocating pro-life/anti-abortion, pro-gun ownership, anti-gay rights, and strong support for the military. A theory has been voiced by several commentators that there seems, at present there seems, to be a drift toward the “left” in the American public, with the gradual acceptance of same-sex marriage, women in combat roles, and concern for intersex equity, but interestingly enough the trend does not include an added support for gun control. These stereotypes don’t always hold up, and in addition there is a growing movement of Independents, voters who decline to state a party affiliation on their voter registration form. So it may be misleading to say that the nation is divided down the middle—but it is a clear indication that across this nation we just don’t all agree on the details of how one should be a good citizen, other than it is a good thing to have a form of government where the people have the opportunity to vote. So if we’re looking for a code of ethics to live by, and even to promote, we should expect that not everyone is going to agree. But what is also commonplace is that we tend to think that those who disagree with us are either stupid, ignorant, or perhaps even evil. The blogosphere is full of such assumptions. And that lends itself to thinking that we, perhaps in fact, are citizens of two cultures within the United States, the culture of liberal values and the culture of conservative values (a pattern known in many other countries with a Western tradition of democracy and right to free speech). Some call it a culture war. So here I have a little recommendation—an introduction of a moral value, if you will: For the sake of a good discussion, whether in the classroom, online, or perhaps just as an internal dialogue with yourself, it may be useful not to jump to the immediate conclusion that people who disagree with you are stupid, ignorant, or evil. As we strive to become a nation of successful diversity, we sometimes forget that moral and political diversity also deserves a place alongside diversity of gender, race, religion, economic background, sexual orientation, and so forth. In other words, people have a right to have a wide variety of opinions, and some of these opinions are arrived at through honest and conscientious deliberation. We have little chance of being able to talk with one another and even learn from one another if we keep thinking that everybody who doesn’t agree with us is automatically wrong or wrongheaded.
On the other hand, an acceptance of the fact that people disagree on moral issues doesn’t have to lead to a moral relativism, or an assumption that there is always another side to everything. Despite our moral differences in this culture, most reasonable people are going to agree on some basic values: In my experience, the majority of Americans are in favor of justice and equality, and against murder, child abuse, racism, sexism, slavery, animal torture, and so forth. In Chapter 3 you’ll find a discussion of ethical relativism, and in Chapter 11 you’ll find a further discussion of the search for common values in a politically diverse culture.
Values, Morals, and Ethics
In its most basic sense, what we value is something we believe is set apart from things that we don’t value or that we value less. When do we first begin to value something? As babies, we live in a world that is divided into what we like and what we don’t like—a binary world of plus and minus, of yes and no. Some psychoanalysts believe we never really get over this early stage, so that some people simply divide the world into what they like or approve of and what they dislike or disapprove of. However, most of us add to that a justification for our preferences or aversions. And this is where the concept of moral values comes in. Having values implies that we have a moral code that we live by, or at least that we tell ourselves we try to live by, a set of beliefs about what constitutes good conduct and a good character. Perhaps equally important, having values implies that we have a conception of what society should be, such as a promoter of values we consider good, a safety net for when things go wrong, an overseer that punishes bad behavior and rewards good behavior, a caregiver for all our basic needs, or a minimalist organization that protects the people against internal and external enemies but otherwise leaves them alone to pursue their own happiness. In Chapter 7 we examine several of these conceptions of social values.
In the late twentieth century the number of college classes in introductory ethics and value theory swelled. When they hear I teach ethics, people who are unfamiliar with how college classes in the subject are taught say, “Good! Our college students really need that!” That response always makes me pause: What do they think I teach? Right from wrong? Of course, we do have discussions about right and wrong, and we can, from time to time, even reach agreement about some moral responses being preferable to other moral responses. If students haven’t acquired a sense of values by the time they’re in college, I fear it’s too late: Psychologists say a child must develop a sense of values by the age of seven to become an adult with a conscience. If the child hasn’t learned by the second grade that other people can feel pain and pleasure, and that one should try not to harm others, that lesson will probably never be truly learned. Fortunately, that doesn’t mean everyone must be taught the same moral lessons by the age of seven—as long as we have some moral background to draw on later, as a sounding board for further ethical reflections, we can come from morally widely diverse homes and still become morally dependable people. A child growing up in a mobster type of family will certainly have acquired a set of morals by the age of seven—but it isn’t necessarily the same set of morals as those acquired by a child in a liberal, secular, humanist family or in a Seventh-Day Adventist family. The point is that all
these children will have their moral center activated and can expand their moral universe. A child who has never been taught any moral lessons may be a sociopath of the future, a person who has no comprehension of how other people feel, no empathy. A case that garnered attention recently, and introduced a new concept, “affluenza,” was the 2013 case of Ethan Couch, then 16 years old, whose drunk driving resulted in the deaths of four people. At his trial, a psychologist testified for the defense that growing up in a very affluent, permissive family had not taught him right from wrong. Whether or not this argument was just a lawyer’s clever trick, it highlighted the possibility that we indeed have to be exposed to ideas of right and wrong as children in order to recognize them as significant later in life. And with the attempted flight of Couch and his mother to Mexico in 2015, it seemed clear that Couch’s lack of understanding that one must take responsibility for one’s actions was something that his mother may not have sufficiently understood, either. In 2016 a Texas judge ordered him to serve 2 years in prison, 180 days for each of the four victims.
If having moral values has to do with brain chemistry, and with simple likes and dislikes, why don’t we turn to the disciplines of neuroscience and psychology for an understanding of values? Why is philosophy the discipline that examines the values issue? That question goes to the core of what philosophy is: Neuroscience can tell us about the physical underpinnings of our mental life and possibly whether our mental reactions have a correlation to the world we live in, but as you will see below, it can’t tell us whether our mental processes are socially appropriate or inappropriate, morally justified or unjustified, and so forth. Neuroscience has recently identified areas in the brain where moral decisions involving empathy take place, but that doesn’t mean that neuroscientists can tell us which moral decisions are more correct than others. Psychology can tell us only what people believe and possibly why they believe it; it can’t make a statement about whether people are justified in believing it. Philosophy’s job, at least in this context, is to question our values; it forces us to provide reasons, and preferably good reasons, for giving our moral approval to one type of behavior and disapproving of another. Philosophy asks the fundamental question Why?, in all its fields, including the field of value theory/ethics. (Box 1.1 gives an overview of the classic branches within philosophy.) Why do we have the values we have? Why do values make some people give up their comfort, even their lives, for a cause, or for other people’s welfare? Why do some people disregard the values of their society for a chosen cause or for personal gain? Is it ever morally appropriate to think of yourself and not of others? Are there ultimate absolute moral values, or are they a matter of personal or cultural choices? Such fundamental questions can be probed by philosophy in a deeper and more fundamental way than by neuroscience or psychology, and we will explore such questions in the upcoming chapters. If having values is such an important feature of our life, should elementary schools teach values, then? It may be just a little too late, if indeed a child’s moral sense is developed by the age of seven, but at least there is a chance it might help; and for children whose parents have done a minimal job of teaching them respect for others, school will probably be the only place they’ll learn it. Some elementary schools are developing such programs. Problems occur, however, when schools begin to teach values with which not all parents agree. We live in a multicultural
Box 1.1 THE FOUR CL ASSIC BRANCHES OF PHILOSOPHY
In the chapter text, you read that philosophy traditionally asks the question Why? This is one of the features that has characterized Western philosophy from its earliest years in Greek antiquity. We generally date Western philosophy from approximately seven hundred years b.c.e./b.c. (“before the common era”/“before Christ”), when some Greek thinkers, such as Thales, Heraclitus, and Parmenides, began to ask questions about what reality truly consists of: Is it the way we perceive it through the senses, or is there an underlying true reality that our intellect can understand? Thales believed the underlying reality was water; Heraclitus believed that it was a form of ever-changing energy; and Parmenides saw true reality as being an underlying realm of permanence, elements that don’t change. We call this form of philosophy metaphysics; in Chapter 8 you will read a brief introduction to Plato’s famous theory of metaphysics, but otherwise the topic of metaphysics has only indirect bearing on the topic of this book. A few centuries after Thales, the next area of philosophy that manifested itself was ethics, with Socrates’ questioning of what is the right way to live (see chapter text). Two generations later the third area of philosophy was introduced, primarily through the writings of Aristotle: logic, the establishing of rules for proper thinking as opposed to fallacious thinking. But the fourth area of Western philosophy didn’t really take hold in the minds of thinkers until some two thousand years later, in the seventeenth century, when René Descartes began to seriously explore what the mind can know: epistemology, or theory of knowledge. All four branches of philosophy are represented today in school curricula and enjoy vibrant debates within the philosophical community. The only branch to have languished somewhat is metaphysics, since modern science has answered some of its ancient questions: We now know
about the subnuclear reality of quantum mechanics. But a classical question of metaphysics remains unanswered by science to this day: What is the nature of the human mind? Do we have a soul that outlives our bodies, or will our self be extinguished with the demise of our brain?
Until the mid–twentieth century, philosophy was usually taught in the West with the underlying assumption that philosophy as such was, by and large, a Western phenomenon. That rather ethnocentric attitude has changed considerably over the last decades. It is now recognized unequivocally among Western scholars that Asian philosophy has its own rich traditions of exploration of metaphysics and ethics in particular; and some philosophers point out that in a sense, all cultures have metaphysics and ethics, even if they have no body of philosophical literature, because their legends, songs, and religious stories will constitute the culture’s view of reality as well as the moral rules and their justifications. As for logic and epistemology, they are not as frequently encountered in non-Western cultures: Indian philosophy has established its own tradition of logic, but epistemology remains a Western philosophical specialty, according to most Western scholars.
To the four classic branches, philosophy has added a number of specialized fields over the centuries, such as philosophy of art (aesthetics), social philosophy, philosophy of religion, political philosophy, philosophy of sports, philosophy of human nature, philosophy of gender, and philosophy of science. What makes these fields philosophical inquiries is their special approach to their subjects; they investigate not only the nature of art, social issues, religion, politics, and so on, but also the theoretical underpinnings of each field, its hidden assumptions and agendas, and its future moral and social pitfalls and promises.
society, and although some parents might like certain topics to be on the school agenda, others certainly would not. Some parents want their children to have early access to sex education, whereas others consider it unthinkable as a school subject. There is nothing in the concept of values that implies we all have to subscribe to exactly the same ones, no matter how strongly we may feel about our own. So, beyond teaching basic values such as common courtesy, perhaps the best schools can do is make students aware of values and value differences and let students learn to argue effectively for their own values, as well as to question them. Schools, in other words, should focus on ethics in addition to morality.
So what is the difference between ethics and morality? Ethics comes from Greek (ethos, character) and morality from Latin (mores, character, custom, or habit). Today, in English as well as in many other Western languages, both words refer to some form of proper conduct. Although we, in our everyday lives, don’t distinguish clearly between morals and ethics, there is a subtle difference: Some people think the word morality has negative connotations, and in fact it does carry two different sets of associations for most of us. The positive ones are guidance, goodness, humanitarianism, and so forth. Among the negative associations are repression, bigotry, persecution—in a word, moralizing. Suppose the introductory ethics course on your campus was labeled “Introduction to Morals.” You would, in all likelihood, expect something different from what you would expect from a course called “Introduction to Ethics” or “Introduction to Values.” The word morality has a slightly different connotation from that of the terms ethics and values. That is because morality usually refers to the moral rules we follow, the values that we have. Ethics is generally defined as theories about those rules; ethics questions and justifies the rules we live by, and, if ethics can find no rational justification for those rules, it may ask us to abandon them. Morality is the stuff our social life is made of—even our personal life—and ethics is the ordering, the questioning, the awareness, the investigation of what we believe: Are we justified in believing it? Is it consistent? Should we remain open to other beliefs or not? If we live by a system of moral rules, we may or may not have understood them or even approved of them, but if we have a code of ethics, we signal to the world that we stand by our values, understand them, and are ready to not only act on them but also defend them with words and deeds.
In other words, it is not enough just to have moral rules; we should, as moral, mature persons, be able to justify our viewpoints with ethical arguments or, at the very least, ask ourselves why we feel this way or that about a certain issue. Ethics, therefore, is much more than a topic in a curriculum. As moral adults, we are required to think about ethics all the time.
Most people, in fact, do just that, even in their teens, because it is also considered a sign of maturity to question authority, at least to a certain extent. If a very young adult is told to be home at 11 p.m., she or he will usually ask, “Why can’t I stay out till midnight?” When we have to make up our minds about whether to study over the weekend or go hiking, we usually try to come up with as many pros and cons as we can. When someone we have put our trust in betrays that trust, we want to know why. All those questions are practical applications of ethics: They question the rules of morality and the breaking of those rules. Although formal training in ethical questions can make us
better at judging moral issues, we are, as adult human beings, already quite experienced just because we already have asked “Why?” a number of times in our lives.
Good and Evil
You have probably heard the “E-word” (evil) recently, in conversation or in the media. And good is surely one of the most frequently used words in the English language. But interestingly, for most of the previous century ethicists preferred to use terms such as “morally acceptable and unacceptable,” or “right versus wrong,” rather than good versus evil. That pattern seems to be changing, and we’ll talk about why in this section.
When terrible things happen to ordinary people, including natural disasters as well as calamities of human origin, we frequently hear stories of people who are not only victims of the disaster, but also subsequent victims of human schemes of violence or fraud. But we also hear about people who go out of their way to help others. During the nuclear crisis in Japan following the earthquake and tsunami, what became known as the Fukushima 50 (actually around 300 volunteers) chose to go in and work in the damaged nuclear reactors, in peril of their lives and certainly exposed to high levels of radiation, for the sake of the community. It was clear that they knew the risk, but also that they volunteered because they felt it was the right thing to do for their community. In 2015, three young American males—two service members and a college student—thwarted a terrorist attack on a high-speed passenger train headed for Paris by tackling and subduing the terrorist, risking their lives in the process; during the December 2015 massacre at the Regional Center building in San Bernardino, carried out by a radicalized Islamist husband-and-wife team, fourteen people died. One of those fourteen, Shannon Johnson, died saving one of his co-workers by covering her body with his own, saying “I’ve got you.” In the Virginia Tech massacre in 2007 in Blacksburg, Virginia, thirty-two students and professors were murdered by a student, Seung-Hui Cho, but many more might have died had it not been for Dr. Liviu Livrescu, a 76-year-old semi-retired professor who blocked the door for Cho until all his students could make their escape through the window. In the end Dr. Livrescu couldn’t hold the door any longer, and Cho burst in and killed him, and subsequently killed himself. Such stories (of which you will hear more in Chapter 4 where we will discuss the phenomena of selfishness and altruism) remind us that dreadful things can happen in the blink of an eye, but also that there are extraordinary people who will rise to the occasion and make decisions that may cost them their lives, for the sake of others. That, to most of us, may be the ultimate form of goodness, but the everyday kindness of a helping hand or a considerate remark shouldn’t be discounted, even if the kind person isn’t endangering his or her life.
There is hardly a word with a broader meaning in the English language than good—we can talk about food tasting good, test results being good, a feeling being good, but also, of course, of actions being good and persons being good, and we mean something different in all these examples. In Box 1.2 you’ll find a discussion of moral and nonmoral values, and “good” fits right into that discussion: It is a value term because it expresses approval, but it can be an approval that has to do
In The Lord of the Rings (2001–3) the concept of evil is symbolized by the Ring. Here the hobbit Smeagol (Andy Serkis) finds the Ring on his birthday (top). Many years later the effects of evil are clearly visible: Smeagol has become Gollum (bottom), a solitary creature whose mind is focused exclusively on the Ring.
Another random document with no related content on Scribd:
CHAPTER XIV
HOW THE MAN OF SENTIMENT SENTIMENTALISED IN A DITCH
He was not to remain long undisturbed, it seemed, for presently upon the stilly air was the faint, regular tapping of a stick that drew gradually nearer, and glancing up he saw an old woman approaching, one who trudged sturdily with the aid of a formidable staff and bore a large wooden basket on her arm; a tall old creature with a great jut of nose and chin and fierce bright eyes that glittered beneath thick brows, whose jetty-black contrasted very strangely with her snow-white hair. But just now these fierce old eyes were dimmed with tears, and more than once she sniffed loud and dolorously; perceiving which and noting how she laboured with the heavy-laden basket, Sir John pocketed his tablets and rose. But, quite lost in her grief, the old creature paused to sob and sniff and wipe away her tears with a corner of her shawl, in the doing of which she let fall her basket, scattering its contents broadcast in the dust. At this calamity she wailed distressfully, and was in the act of bending her old joints to collect her property when she was aware of one who did this for her, a slender, very nimble young man, at sight of whom she forgot her troubles a while, watching him in mute surprise, yet quick to heed the white delicacy of these hands as they darted here and there collecting the bundles of herbs and simples with the other more homely vegetables that lay so widely scattered. Thus Sir John, happening to glance up as he stooped for a large cabbage, met the fixed scrutiny of a pair of black eyes, so fierce and keenly direct beneath their jutting brows that he stared back, surprised and a little disconcerted.
“My good dame, why d’ye stare so?” he questioned.
“I dream, young sir! Your bright eyes do ha’ set me a-dreamin’ o’ other days ... better days ... when the world was younger ... an’ kinder. Old I be an’ tur’ble lonesome, but I ha’ my dreams ... ’tis arl the years ha’ left me.... But why must ye meddle wi’ the likes o’ me?” ... she demanded in sudden ferocity. “Why don’t ’ee cross y’r fingers or mak’ ‘the horns’ agin me?”
“Why should I?” he inquired, wondering.
“Because they du say as I’ve the ‘evil eye’ an’ can blight a man wi’ a look as easy as I can a pig ... or a cow.”
“To be sure your eyes are very strange and bright,” he answered gently, “and must have been very beautiful once, like yourself—when the world was younger.”
“Beautiful,” she repeated in changed tone; and her eyes grew less keen, the harsh lines of her fierce, old face softening wonderfully “Beautiful?” said she again. “Aye, so I was, years agone ... though there be few as would believe it o’ me now an’ fewer eyes sharp enough t’ see.... An’ you bean’t fruttened o’ me then, young man?”
“No, I am not frightened,” answered Sir John.
“Why then,” quoth she, “when you’m done wi’ that cabbage o’ mine, there be an onion over yonder, agin the dik!” Sir John deposited the cabbage, and having retrieved the errant onion, added this also to the well-laden basket.
“That is all, I think?” said he, glancing about.
“Aye!” she nodded. “An’ it be plain t’ know you be a stranger hereabouts. There bean’t a man nor bye, aye, an’ mortal few o’ the women, would ha’ stooped to du so much for poor old Penelope Haryott, I reckon.”
“And pray why not?”
“Because they say I be a witch, an’ they be arl main fruttened o’ me, an’ them as say they ain’t, du hate me most. Aye, me! I’ve been thrattened wi’ the fire afore now; an’ only las’ March, an’ main cold it were, they was for a-duckin’ o’ me in the Cuckmere.... Ah, an’ they’d ha’ done it tu if Passon Hartop ’adn’t galloped over tu Alfriston an’
fetched Sir Hector MacLean as knew me years ago, an’ Jarge Potter as I’ve dandled a babe on my knee. Sir Hector were main fierce again the crowd an’ swore t’ cut any man’s throat as dared tetch me, an’ Jarge Potter ’ad on his old frieze coat—so the crowd let me go ... they ain’t tried to harm me since.... But ’tis very sure you be a stranger in these parts, young man.”
“Indeed, yes!” sighed Sir John, once more oppressed by the sense of his responsibility and of the duties left undone.
“An’ yet there be a look about ’ee, young man, as do whisper me you was barn here in Sussex an’ not s’ fur away, I reckon.”
“Oh ... begad!” he exclaimed, starting. “What should make you think so, pray?”
“Y’r hands, young sir, the high cock o’ your chin, y’r pretty eyes ... they do mind me of other eyes as looked into mine long afore you was barn ... when the world was happier.... Though ’e were bigger’n you, young man ... so tall an’ noble-lookin’! Alack, ’twas long ago an’ the world be changed for the worse since then—’specially High Dering! Aye, me! I’ll be a-goin’, young sir, thankin’ ye for your kindness to a solitary old woman.”
“How far are you going?” he questioned.
“Only to the village yonder.”
“This basket is much too heavy for you.”
“Lud, young master, I do be stronger than I look!” she answered, with a mirthless laugh. “Aye, tur’ble strong I be or I should ha’ died years agone, I reckon. So doan’t ’ee trouble, sir ... besides, folk ’ud stare t’ see s’fine a young man along o’ me, an’ a-carryin’ my old trug an’ arl ... so let be!”
Sir John smiled, took up the basket, reached his stick whence it leaned against the stile and set off with old Penelope Haryott, suiting his pace to hers and talking with such blithe ease that old Penelope, forgetting her rustic pride at last, talked in her turn, as she might have done “when the world was younger and better.”
“Ah yes, I mind Sir Hector years agone, when he were jest Mr Hector an’ friend t’ Sir John Dering—him as was the ‘real’ Sir John as lived at ‘the gert house’ yonder an’ married here ... an’ marched away t’ the wars wi’ Mr. Hector, both s’fine in their red coats, and him s’handsome an’ gay ... him as was killed an’ never come marchin’ back.”
“Ah!” exclaimed Sir John as she paused. “So you knew Sir John Dering, the Sir John who was killed years ago in Flanders? Pray tell me of him.”
“An’ why should I?” quoth the old woman in sudden anger “He’s been dead long years an’ forgot, I reckon. But when he lived the world was a better place ... ’specially High Dering! Aye, he was ... a man!”
“And what,” questioned Sir John wistfully, “what of the new Sir John Dering?”
Old Penelope spat contemptuously and trudged on a little faster.
“Take care o’ my old trug, young man,” she admonished; “the ’andle be main loose! Aye, me, if my troubles was no ’eavier than that theer trug I’d bear’em j’yful!”
“Are you so greatly troubled, then?” he asked gently.
“Ah, more’n my share, I reckon! And an old woman so solitary as I be must allus go full o’ sorrow!”
“Will you tell me some of your sorrows, old Penelope?”
“Why should I?”
“Because I ask reverently and respect you.”
“Respect! Me?” she muttered. “Respect? O kind Lord, ’tis a strange word in my old ears! Folks mostly curse me ... the children throws stones at me! ’Tis an ill thing to be named a witch ... an’ all because I can see deeper and further than most fules, can read the good an’ evil in faces an’ know a sight about yarbs an’ simples. An’ they’re fruttened o’ me, the fules ... ah, an’ they need be, some on ’em—’specially one!”
“You were weeping when I saw you first, Penelope; yet tears do not come easily with you, I judge.”
“Tears?” she exclaimed fiercely “An’ yet I’ve shed s’ many ’tis gert wonder there be any left. ’Tis wonnerful how much one woman can weep in one lifetime, I reckon.”
“And why did you weep to-day?”
“’Tidn’t no manner o’ business o’ yourn, young man!” she exclaimed bitterly.
“Why, then, pray forgive me!” he answered, with a little bow; at this she stared and immediately spoke in changed voice.
“I wep’, sir, because this day week I’m to be turned out o’ doors wi’ never a roof to shelter me—unless some o’ the neighbours offers— which they won’t ... Lord, tak’ care o’ the trug, young man, if ye swing it so fierce ’twill go to pieces!”
“Why are you being turned out?”
“Because they be arl fruttened o’ me—an’ him most of arl——”
“Whom do you mean by ‘him’?”
But old Penelope tramped on unheeding, only she muttered to herself fiercely.
“Do you dread the future so greatly, Penelope?”
“No!” she answered sturdily. “I bean’t fruttened o’ now’t but fire ... an’ dogs!”
“Dogs?” he questioned.
“Aye, young man, they du set ’em on me sometimes, ’tis why I carry this gert staff ... killed a dog wi’ it once, I did—though I were badly bit! So they clapped me in the stocks, the dog was valleyble, y’ see, an’ chanced to belong to Lord Sayle, him as du live at the great ’ouse ’Friston way.”
Talking thus, they became aware of leisured hoof-strokes behind them, and, turning to stare, old Penelope pointed suddenly at the approaching rider with her long staff.
“Yonder ’e comes!” she whispered fiercely; “him as ought t’ be dead an’ gibbeted ... him as be afeart o’ me!”
Glancing round in turn, Sir John beheld a man bestriding a large, plump steed, a man who rode at a hand-pace, apparently lost in thought; thus Sir John had full time to observe him narrowly as he approached.
He seemed a prosperous and highly respectable man, for he went in broadcloth and fine linen; but his garments, devoid of all embellishings, were of sober hue, so that, looked at from behind, he might have been an itinerant preacher with a hint of the Quaker, but seen from in front, the narrow eyes, predatory nose, vulperine mouth and fleshy chin stamped him as being like nothing in life but himself.
Slowly he approached, until, suddenly espying the old woman, he urged his somnolent horse to quicker gait and rode towards her, brandishing the stick he carried.
“Damned hag,” cried he, “you ought to burn!”
“Dirty twoad,” she retorted, “you’d ought to hang!” At this, the man struck at her passionately, and, being out of reach, spurred his powerful horse as if to ride her down; but Sir John, setting by the basket, sprang and caught the bridle.
“Steady, sir, steady!” quoth he mildly.
“Mind your own business!” cried the horseman.
“Faith, sir,” answered Sir John ruefully, “’tis high time I did, ’twould seem. And indeed I propose doing so, but in my own fashion. And first I desire to learn why you ride the king’s highway to the common danger——”
“Oh, and who the devil might you be?”
“One who hath played divers rôles, sir,” answered Sir John. “Just at present I find myself a Man o’ Sentiment, full o’ loving-kindness, especially to sorrowful old age——”
“What the devil!” exclaimed the horseman, staring.
“Come then, sir, let us together bare our heads in homage to Age, Sorrow and Womanhood in the person of this much-enduring Mistress Haryott!” and off came Sir John’s hat forthwith.
“Are ye mad?” demanded the other scornfully. “Are ye mad or drunk, my lad?”
“Sir, a Man of Sentiment is never——”
“Curse your sentiment! Let me warn ye that yon hag is a notorious evil-liver and a damned witch——”
“Which as a Man of Sentiment——”
“Hold y’r tongue, d’ye hear! She’s a witch, I tell ye, so tak’ my advice, my lad, throw that old trug o’ her’n over the hedge and leave her to the devil! And now loose my bridle; I’m done.”
“But I am not, sir!” answered Sir John. “You attempted to strike a woman in my presence, and have dared allude to me twice as your ‘lad’—two very heinous offences——”
“Loose my bridle or ’twill be the worse for ye. D’ye know who I am?”
“Judging by your right eye, sir, its rainbow colouring, I opine you must be Mr. James Sturton——”
“Damn your insolence—leggo my bridle!”
But instead of complying, Sir John gave a sudden twist to the bit, whereupon the plump and somnolent steed waked to sudden action, insomuch that Mr. Sturton was nearly unseated and his hat tumbled off; whereupon Sir John deftly skewered it upon the end of his stick and tossed it over the hedge; and old Penelope, watching its brief flight, uttered a single screech of laughter and was immediately silent again.
Mr. Sturton, having quieted his horse, raised his stick and struck viciously, but Sir John, deftly parrying the blow, answered it with a thrust, a lightning riposte that took his aggressor full upon fleshy chin. Mr. Sturton dropped his stick, clapped hand to chin and, seeing
his own blood, spurred madly upon Sir John, who, in escaping the lashing hoofs, tripped and fell into the ditch.
“Let that learn ye!” cried Mr Sturton, exultantly shaking his fist. “A ditch is the proper place for you, my lad.... I only hope as you’ve broke a bone.”
“Thank you,” answered Sir John, sitting up, and groping for his hat, “I find myself very well, for:
Though in posture unheroic You behold me still a stoic. And, further, here’s a truth, sir, which is: There are places worse than ditches!
Indeed, Mr. Sturton,” he added, leaning back in the ditch and folding his arms, “’tis in my mind that you may find yourself yearning passionately for a good, dry ditch one o’ these days.”
“Bah!” cried the other contemptuously. “If ye can crawl—crawl and bring me my hat.”
“The heavens,” answered Sir John, pointing thither with graceful flourish, “the heavens shall fall first, sir.”
“Ha, now—look’ee! You’ll bring me my hat, young man, or I’ll march you and yon vile old beldam into Dering and ha’ ye clapped into the stocks together for assault on the highway! D’ye hear?”
“Sir,” answered Sir John, “a fiddlestick!”
Uttering an angry exclamation, Mr. Sturton whipped a pistol from his holster, but as he did so, old Penelope whirled her long staff which, missing him by a fraction, took effect upon his horse, whereupon this much-enduring animal promptly bolted and galloped furiously away with Mr. Sturton in a cloud of dust.
“Lord ha’ mercy!” gasped old Penelope as the galloping hoof-beats blurred and died away. “Lord, what ’ave I done?”
“Removed an offence by a mere flourish o’ your magic wand, like the fairy godmother you are!” answered Sir John. “Mistress
Penelope, accept my thanks—I salute you!” And, standing up in the ditch, he bowed gravely.
“Ha’ done, young man, ha’ done!” she cried distressfully “He’ll raise the village again’ me ... he’ll ha’ me in the stocks again—an’ arl along o’ you! An’ I can’t bear they stocks like I used to ... they cramps my old bones s’cruel.... O Lord ha’ mercy! The stocks!” And, leaning on her staff, she bowed her white head and sobbed miserably.
In a moment Sir John was out of the ditch and, standing beside her, laid one white hand upon her shoulder, patting it gently
“Penelope,” said he softly, “don’t weep! No man shall do you violence.... I swear none shall harm you any more so be comforted!”
“An’ who be you t’ promise s’much?” she demanded fiercely
“One who will keep his word——”
“I be so old,” she wailed—“so old an’ lonesome an’ weary of ’t all.”
“But very courageous!” he added gently. “And I think, Penelope, nay, I’m sure there are better days coming for you—and me. So come, let us go on, confident in ourselves and the future.”
And taking stick and basket in one hand, he slipped the other within his aged companion’s arm and they tramped on again.
“You speak mighty bold, young man!” said she after a while, with another of her keen glances. “Aye, an’ look mighty bold—why?”
“Perhaps because I feel mighty bold!” he answered lightly.
“Aye, like ye did when he knocked ye into the ditch, young man!”
“The ditch?” repeated Sir John. “Aye, begad, the ditch! ’S heart, it needed but this!” And here he laughed so blithely that old Penelope stared and, forgetting her recent tears, presently smiled.
“Ye tumbled so ’mazin’ sudden, young man,” she nodded. “An’ then I never ’eerd no one talk po’try in a dik’ afore.”
“And you probably never will again, Penelope. The occasion was unique and my extempore rhymes none too bad.”
“Eh—eh, young man, did ye mak’ ’em up a-settin’ in t’ dik’ arl out o’ y’r head? Lord!”
So they reached the village at last, its deep-thatched cottages nestled beneath the sheltering down; a quiet, sleepy place where a brook gurgled pleasantly and rooks cawed lazily amid lofty, ancient trees; a place of peace, it seemed, very remote from the world.
But, as they went, rose a stir, a flutter, a growing bustle; heads peered from casements, from open doorways and dim interiors; children ceased their play to point, a woman laughed shrilly, men, home-coming from the fields, stood to stare, to laugh, to hoot and jeer; and foremost, among a group of loungers before the ancient inn, Sir John espied Mr. Sturton.
And thus amid hoots, jeers and derisive laughter came Sir John to High Dering.
CHAPTER XV
WHICH INTRODUCES A FRIEZE COAT AND ITS WEARER, ONE GEORGE POTTER
“Old gammer du ha’ found ’ersen a man at last!” cried a voice.
“Ah, the danged owd witch du ha’ ’witched hersel’ a sweet’eart fur sure!” roared another.
“An’ sech a nice-lookin’ young man an’ arl!” quoth a matron with a fat baby in her arms, whom Sir John saluted with a bow, whereupon she hid blushing face behind her plump baby.
But as they progressed the crowd grew and, with increasing number, their attitude waxed more threatening; laughter changed to angry mutterings, clods and stones began to fly.
“I waarned ’ee ’ow ’twould be!” quoth old Penelope bitterly. “You’d best leave me an’ run, young man, quick—up the twitten yonder!” Even as she spoke, Sir John was staggered by a well-aimed clod and his hat spun from his head. Setting down the basket, he turned and stood fronting the crowd frowning a little, chin uptilted, serene of eye. Foremost among their assailants was a burly young fellow, chiefly remarkable for a very wide mouth and narrow-set eyes, towards whom Sir John pointed with his holly-stick.
“Pray, Mistress Haryott,” he inquired in his clear, ringing tones, “who is yonder ill-conditioned wight?”
“That?” cried old Penelope in fierce scorn. “It be Tom Simpson, a Lon’on lad ... one o’ th’ Excise as creeps an’ crawls an’ spies on better men——”
“Oh, do I, then!” snarled the burly young man. “I’ll knock your dummed eye out for that, I will!” And he reached for a stone, but
checked suddenly as Sir John strode towards him carrying the hollystick much as if it had been a small-sword.
“Talking of eyes,” quoth Sir John, with a graceful flourish of the stick, “drop that stone, lest I feel it necessary to blind you!” and he made an airy pass at the face of the young man, who leapt back so precipitately that he stumbled and fell, whereupon the crowd, roaring with laughter at his discomfiture, pressed nearer, eager for diversion.
“Doan’t let ’un bloind ’ee, lad!” cried one.
“’E bean’t so big as ’ee, Tom! Tak’ a ’edge-stake tu un!”
“Noa, tak’ my ol’ bat; it du be a good ’eavy ’un, Tom!” cried a second.
The burly young man, finding himself thus the centre of observation, snatched the proffered stick, squared his shoulders and approached Sir John in very ferocious and determined manner, but halted, just out of reach, to spit upon his palm and take fresh hold upon his bludgeon; whereupon the crowd encouraged him on this wise:
“Knock ’is little wig off, Tom!”
“Poke ’is eye out, lad!”
“Aim at ’is nob!”
“Go fur ’is legs!”
Suddenly the burly young man sprang, aiming a terrific blow, but, instead of attempting a parry, Sir John leapt nimbly aside, and the young man, impelled by the force of his stroke, once more stumbled and fell; and then before he could rise, old Penelope commenced to belabour him with her long staff as he lay, panting out maledictions with every blow until the crowd, laughing, shouting, cursing, surged forward to the rescue. Drawing the fierce and breathless old creature behind him, Sir John, seeing escape impossible, faced the oncoming menace strung and quivering for desperate action, while the crowd lashed itself to fury by such cries as:
“Down wi’ the young cock!”
“Scrag the owd witch, lads: to the watter wi’ ’er!”
“Aye, to the river with ’em—both of ’em!” cried Mr. Sturton, loudest of all.
And then forth from one of those narrow lanes, or rather passages that are known as “twittens,” sauntered a man in a short, frieze coat, vast of pocket and button, a wide-shouldered, comely man whose face, framed between neatly trimmed whiskers, wore an air of guileless good-nature. Guilelessness indeed! It was in his eyes despite their lurking twinkle, in the uptrend of his firm lips, the tilt of his nose, his close-cropped whiskers and square chin. Guilelessness beamed in the brass buttons of his short-skirted frieze coat, it was in the very creases of his garments, it seemed to enfold him from boots and gaiters to the crown of his weather-worn hat, it was in the tones of his soft yet resonant voice when he spoke:
“Lor’ love Potter, Mr. Sturton, sir, but ’oo’s been an’ give ye that theer tur’ble eye? Arl black it be, sir, leastways where it bean’t black ’tis green. An’ swole, sir! Lor’ love George Potter’s limbs, it du be aswellin’ an’ a-puffin’ of itself up that proud, sir! ’Tis most alarmin’, Mr. Sturton! Shame on ye, neighbours; can’t none on ye du nothin’ fur poor Mr. Sturton’s ogle—look at ’ee——” But, uttering a fierce imprecation, Mr Sturton turned his back, pushed his way angrily into the inn, and slammed the door behind him.
“I never seen a blacker eye, never——”
“Don’t go fur to blame we, Jarge Potter!” quoth a greybeard. “’Tidn’t none o’ our doin’—no!”
“Then what be the trouble, neighbours? What’s to du, good folk?” inquired Mr. Potter.
“It ain’t none o’ your business anyway!” retorted the burly young man sullenly. “We be honest folks, which be more than some can say with y’r poachin’, ah, an’ smugglin’!”
“Hold thy tongue, lad!” cried the greybeard, plucking the burly young man’s arm. “Don’t ’ee see as Jarge be wearin’ ’is ol’ frieze coat?”
“What do I care for ’is old coat!”
“That’s because ye be fullish an’ strange ’ereabouts an’ doan’t know Jarge.”
“Neighbours,” said Mr. Potter in his deep, leisured tones, his placid gaze roving from face to face, “you arl do know as Potter be a peaceable man, so here’s Potter a-beggin’ an’ a-pleadin’ o’ ye to leave old Pen alone—or I’m afeard some on ye might get ’urted— bad, I reckon!” As he spoke, Mr. Potter’s powerful hands disappeared into the deep pockets of his frieze coat, and he took a leisurely pace forward. “Simpson, my lad,” quoth he, nodding kindly at the burly young man, “your mouth’s so oncommon large as you’ll swaller yourself, boots an’ arl, one of these days if ye open it s’wide! So run along, my lad! ’Ome be the word, neighbours; off wi’ ye now —arl on ye. I bean’t a-goin’ t’ plead twice wi’ no one.”
Mr. Potter’s brow was smooth, guilelessness seemed to radiate and beam from his person, but, seeing how the crowd forthwith scattered and melted away, the burly young man betook himself off likewise, muttering darkly.
Then Mr. Potter turned in his unhurried fashion to look at Sir John, and the smile that lurked in the corners of his mouth slowly broadened.
“Young sir,” said he, touching his hat, “who you be or what, bean’t no consarn o’ mine nohow, but, sir, you stood up for a old ’ooman as aren’t got many to tak’ ’er part, d’ye see, an’ so ’ere’s Potter athankin’ of you—an’ that is my business, I rackon.”
“Indeed, Mr. Potter, ’twould seem I have to thank you also, you—or your coat——”
“Coat?” repeated Mr. Potter, glancing down at the garment in question as if mildly surprised to behold it. “Aye, to be sure—’tis a old jacket as I use in my trade, d’ye see——”
“A free-trade, I think?” added Sir John.
“Lor’ love ’ee, sir,” sighed Mr. Potter, opening his guileless eyes a trifle wider, “doan’t ’ee tak’ no ’eed o’ what that theer young Simpson
says——”
“Mr. Potter,” quoth Sir John, smiling, “a week ago I was shaking hands with Captain Sharkie Nye aboard the True Believer, and I should like to shake yours.”
“What, be you the young gen’leman as crossed wi’ Sir Hector?”
“That same. And my name is Derwent.”
“Why, Mr. Derwent, sir, that du alter the case, I rackon. So theer be Potter’s ’and, sir, and heartily! Ah, an’ yonder be old Penelope abeckonin’ ... her will curse we shameful if us du keep her waitin’ ... so come ’long, sir.”
“Aye, come y’r ways, du—both on ye!” cried the old creature imperiously. “’Tidn’t often I ’as comp’ny, so I’ll brew ye a dish o’ tay ——”
“Tea?” exclaimed Sir John.
“Aye, all the way from Chaney, young man! Tay as costes forty shillin’ a pound an’ more up to Lunnon—tak’ care o’ my old trug! This way—down twitten!”
She led them down a narrow way between the walls of cottages and gardens, and at last to a very small cottage indeed, a forlorn little structure, its garden trampled, its broken window-panes stuffed with old rags to exclude the elements, itself all dilapidation from rotting thatch to crumbling doorstep.
“And is this your home?” cried Sir John, very much aghast.
“It be, young man. They bruk’ all my lattices months agone, an’ Mr. Sturton won’t put in no more. The chimbley smokes an’ the thatch leaks an’ I gets the ager bad, but it be my home an’ I love every brick. For ’twas here I were born, here I loved and lost, here I hoped to die, but Maaster Sturton be fur turning o’ me out next month ... bean’t ’e, Jarge?”
“’E be,” answered Mr. Potter softly, “dang ’im!”
“Come in, young man, an’ you tu, Jarge—come in; it du be betterlookin’ inside than out.” And indeed, once the door was shut—a
particularly stout and ponderous door, Sir John noticed—the small, heavily beamed chamber was cosy and homelike, very orderly and clean, from the polished copper kettle on the hob to the china ornaments upon the mantel.
And now Mr. Potter reached a hand within the mysteries of the frieze coat and drew thence a couple of plump rabbits.
“Found ’em s’marnin’, Pen,” he nodded. “An’ here,” he continued, groping deeper within vast pocket, “’ere be a—no, that be wire ... ’ere—no, that be ’baccy for ’Osea ... ah, ’ere be a lump o’ pork t’ go wi’ ’em, Pen.”
“Thank’ee kindly, Jarge! An’ would ’ee moind a-skinnin’ of ’em whiles I tidies myself up a bit?”
“Heartily, Pen.”
“An’ you, young man, poke up the fire an’ put on the kittle t’ bile ... there be a pump in the yard.”
Having performed these duties, Sir John, seating himself on a bucket beside the pump, watched Mr. Potter deftly operate upon the rabbits, and there ensued the following conversation:
M . P : Stayin’ ’ereabouts, sir?
S J : At the ‘Dering Arms.’
M . P : Stayin’ long, sir?
S J : I hope so.
M . P : Why, so du I ... seein’ as you be known to Sharkie an’ Sir ’Ector. And, besides, old Pen du ha’ took to ye fair amazin’ ... an’ she’s an eye like a nawk ’as old Pen, aye, sharp as a gimblet it be. An’ she’s took to ye, d’ye see, sir.
S J : I feel truly and deeply honoured.
M . P : Well, you stood up for ’er s’arternoon agin them fules as meant mischief.
S J : She seems to have suffered more than her share.
M . P : Suffered? Sir, Potter be a peaceable man an’ bloodshed contrariwise to ’is natur’ no matter what you ’appen to hear ... but there be some folk as I’d tak’ a deal o’ j’y to skin, d’ye see, like this ’ere! (Mr. Potter held up a newly skinned and pinkly nude rabbit.)
S J : Whom do you mean?
M . P : Ah! ’oo indeed, sir? Potter knows, but Potter’s mum!
S J : And yet I think I could guess, if I tried.
M . P : Why, ye may guess, sir—this be a free country —leastways, fules say so.
S J : One, I think, must be Mr. James Sturton. Am I right?
M . P : Why, as to that, sir, I answers plain and to the point as there be nobody nowhere breathin’ as can get s’much flavour into a jugged ’are ekal to old Pen—except Peter Bunkle as keeps the ‘Cross’ over tu Alfriston.
S J : And the second is Lord Sayle. Am I wrong?
M . P : Why, as to that, sir, Potter don’t say nothing. Du ’ee know Lord Sayle?
S J : I have met him.
M . P : Friend o’ yourn, sir?
S J : So much so that I have determined to drive him out of the country, or kill him.
(Here Mr. Potter dropped the rabbit.)
M . P : Well ... love my limbs! Kill—hist! But ... but you, sir? Axing your pardon, but you aren’t got the look of a killer.
S J : Thank you, Mr. Potter, I rejoice to hear it.
M . P : But—ki—hist! He be pretty big and pretty fierce, sir, an’ you, axing y’r pardon, ain’t exactly——
S J : An elephant or a tiger—and yet I feel myself perfectly able to accomplish one or the other, Mr. Potter.
M . P : Well, love my eyes! He be a fightin’ man too, sir! Somebody stuck a sword into him lately, I hear, but it didn’t do no good; he be as well and ’earty as ever. Now if—hist!
(Here Mr. Potter paused, finger on lip, to glance stealthily around.)
S J : If what, Mr. Potter?
M . P : (Drawing near and speaking in hushed voice) If you be ... set on a-doin’ of it ... very determined on ... the deed, sir, your best way is to—hist! A pistol ... no, a musket ... some good dark night. Hist—Potter’s mum!
S J : You don’t love him, I think?
M . P : Love him? Well, there be things ’as ’appened ’ereabouts as no one can’t swear agin nobody, d’ye see, an’ yet ... old Pen knows more than she dare speak, I rackon, an’ Potter ain’t blind nor yet deaf.
S J : What kind of things?
M . P : Well, theer was poor Dick Hobden as went awalkin’ one evenin’ Windover way wi’ Lucy Price, a rare handsome lass. Poor Dick were found stone dead next day, but the lass vanished an’ nobody never seen her no more, nor never will, I reckon.
S J : Vanished?
M . P : Ay, like Mary Beal as disappeared and came back and drownded of ’erself, pore lass. There was Ruth Wicks as likewise vanished an’ was found weeks arterwards singin’ in the dark atop o’ Windover ... died
mad, she did. There was other lasses as disappeared from Wilmington an’ Litlin’ton an’ never come back.
S J : A hateful tale!
M . P : It be, sir.
S J : And whom do you suspect?
M . P : Mum for that, sir! But there be folk as Potter would be j’yful to ’ave the skinnin’ of——
S J : You mean my Lord Sayle and Sturton——
M . P : Hist—sir! Speak soft! I don’t mean nothin’. Only what one bids t’other obeys.... And now Lord Sayle swears he’ll ruin all on us—every man an’ bye, ah, wumman, maid an’ babe, not forgettin’ wives an’ widders.
S J : How so?
M . P : He’s took an oath to put down “the trade,” d’ye see. Potter be a inoffensive creater’ as never drawed steel in his life—except mebbe now and then—I prefers a short bat ... and never fired a shot in all my days—except p’r’aps once or twice an’ then only when com-pelled.... Ah, a peaceable man be Potter, but....
Here Mr Potter laid finger to lip and looked slantwise at Sir John beneath lifted eyebrow. And then old Penelope called them; and, glancing round, Sir John was amazed to behold her clad in a sumptuous gown whose voluminous silken folds lent her a strangely arresting dignity, while upon her snowy hair was a mob cap marvellously belaced.
“Aye, it be real silk, young man!” quoth she, with a little shake in her voice. “List to it rustle!” And sighing ecstatically, she spread out the rich folds with her gnarled old fingers. “There bean’t a grander dress nowhere.... Jarge give it me las’ Christmas. ’Tidn’t often I wears it, no ... but when I die, I’ll be buried in it—won’t I, Jarge?”
“Aye, aye, Pen!” nodded Mr Potter “But, Lord—’oo’s a-talkin’ o’ dyin’! Be the kittle abilin’?”
“Aye, lad, tea’s ready As for you, young man, if you’ll drink wi’ me as they name witch, an’ bean’t fruttened lest I blast ’ee wi’ a look o’ my eye—come your ways to tea.”
Following her into the cottage, Sir John beheld yet other unexpected wonders, as the handleless cups of exquisite ware, the beautiful Chinese teapot, the tray of priceless Chinese lacquer.
“Aha, you may stare, young man!” nodded old Penelope. “There bean’t a lady in arl the land can show ’ee sech chaney as mine.... Jarge give it tu me!”
“Why, ye see, sir,” added Mr. Potter apologetically, “I bean’t married!”
“An’ look at the lace in my cap, young man ... real French point— arl from Jarge.”
“Why, ye see, sir,” quoth Mr. Potter again, “I aren’t got no sweet’eart!”
And thus Sir John Dering, sitting between old Penelope Haryott the witch, and Mr. George Potter the guileless, drank smuggled tea out of smuggled china, talked and listened, asked questions and answered them, and enjoyed it all uncommonly well.