Instant download The philosophy and politics of aesthetic experience: german romanticism and critica

Page 1


The

Philosophy and Politics of Aesthetic Experience: German Romanticism and Critical Theory 1st

Edition Nathan Ross (Auth.)

Visit to download the full and correct content document: https://textbookfull.com/product/the-philosophy-and-politics-of-aesthetic-experience-g erman-romanticism-and-critical-theory-1st-edition-nathan-ross-auth/

More products digital (pdf, epub, mobi) instant download maybe you interests ...

Romanticism, Hellenism, and the Philosophy of Nature

William S. Davis

https://textbookfull.com/product/romanticism-hellenism-and-thephilosophy-of-nature-william-s-davis/

Romanticism Philosophy and Literature Michael N.

Forster

https://textbookfull.com/product/romanticism-philosophy-andliterature-michael-n-forster/

Romanticism, Philosophy, and Literature Michael N. Forster (Editor)

https://textbookfull.com/product/romanticism-philosophy-andliterature-michael-n-forster-editor/

Badiou and the German Tradition of Philosophy Jan Völker

https://textbookfull.com/product/badiou-and-the-german-traditionof-philosophy-jan-volker/

When Art Disrupts Religion Aesthetic Experience and the Evangelical Mind 1st Edition Philip S. Francis

https://textbookfull.com/product/when-art-disrupts-religionaesthetic-experience-and-the-evangelical-mind-1st-edition-philips-francis/

Hannah Arendt’s Aesthetic Politics: Freedom and the Beautiful Jim Josefson

https://textbookfull.com/product/hannah-arendts-aestheticpolitics-freedom-and-the-beautiful-jim-josefson/

The Thought of Bernard Stiegler Capitalism Technology and the Politics of Spirit 1st Edition Ross Abbinnett

https://textbookfull.com/product/the-thought-of-bernard-stieglercapitalism-technology-and-the-politics-of-spirit-1st-editionross-abbinnett/

Aesthetic Pursuits: Essays in Philosophy of Art 1st Edition Jerrold Levinson

https://textbookfull.com/product/aesthetic-pursuits-essays-inphilosophy-of-art-1st-edition-jerrold-levinson/

The Sociolinguistics of Hip-Hop as Critical Conscience: Dissatisfaction and Dissent 1st Edition Andrew S. Ross

https://textbookfull.com/product/the-sociolinguistics-of-hip-hopas-critical-conscience-dissatisfaction-and-dissent-1st-editionandrew-s-ross/

The Philosophy and Politics of Aesthetic Experience

GERMAN ROMANTICISM AND CRITICAL THEORY

NATHAN ROSS

Political Philosophy and Public Purpose

Series Editor

Michael J. Thompson

William Paterson University USA

This series offers books that seek to explore new perspectives in social and political criticism. Seeing contemporary academic political theory and philosophy as largely dominated by hyper-academic and overly-technical debates, the books in this series seek to connect the politically engaged traditions of philosophical thought with contemporary social and political life. The idea of philosophy emphasized here is not as an aloof enterprise, but rather a publicly-oriented activity that emphasizes rational reflection as well as informed praxis.

More information about this series at http://www.springer.com/series/14542

The Philosophy and Politics of Aesthetic Experience

German Romanticism and Critical Theory

Oklahoma City University

Oklahoma City, Oklahoma, USA

Political Philosophy and Public Purpose

ISBN 978-3-319-52303-3 ISBN 978-3-319-52304-0 (eBook)

DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-52304-0

Library of Congress Control Number: 2017933901

© The Editor(s) (if applicable) and The Author(s) 2017

This work is subject to copyright. All rights are solely and exclusively licensed by the Publisher, whether the whole or part of the material is concerned, specifically the rights of translation, reprinting, reuse of illustrations, recitation, broadcasting, reproduction on microfilms or in any other physical way, and transmission or information storage and retrieval, electronic adaptation, computer software, or by similar or dissimilar methodology now known or hereafter developed.

The use of general descriptive names, registered names, trademarks, service marks, etc. in this publication does not imply, even in the absence of a specific statement, that such names are exempt from the relevant protective laws and regulations and therefore free for general use. The publisher, the authors and the editors are safe to assume that the advice and information in this book are believed to be true and accurate at the date of publication. Neither the publisher nor the authors or the editors give a warranty, express or implied, with respect to the material contained herein or for any errors or omissions that may have been made. The publisher remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Cover design by Fatima Jamadar

Printed on acid-free paper

This Palgrave Macmillan imprint is published by Springer Nature

The registered company is Springer International Publishing AG

The registered company address is: Gewerbestrasse 11, 6330 Cham, Switzerland

M

F

The Philosophy and Politics of Aesthetic Experience: German Romanticism and Critical Theory

The relation between aesthetics and philosophy, and between aesthetics and a critical form of social and political philosophy, is a topic of declining concern. Contemporary political philosophy, long under the spell of analytic modes of reasoning, has cast such questions aside. But it is important to note that this was a major thread in the history of German philosophy. It encompassed not only classical German thought but also, well into the twentieth century, the fields of critical theory as well. At stake in reclaiming the link between aesthetics and critical reason is the ability to stave off the increasing dominance of analytic reason, of instrumental rationality, and one-dimensional thought. At stake is the possibility to reclaim a critical culture as well as a kind of art that speaks to human concerns and the social and political context that affects those concerns. The idea of a politics of aesthetics experience, which Nathan Ross asks us to explore and to reconsider, is therefore one that should command our attention. Classical German philosophy was deeply marked by its experience of the discovery of Greek and Roman art. The ideals of humanism opened up to an otherwise pious and Protestant world a new sensuousness, a liberation of aesthetic and philosophical ideals, no less than a new sensibility in morals and politics. German Romanticism was a result of this movement in ideas and this new shift in aesthetic and philosophical vision. Johann Joachim Winckelmann’s 1764 work Geschichte der Kunst des Alterthums, or History of Art in Antiquity, was an opening to this idea of the power of art and its entwinement with social, political, and historical reality. Winckelmann opened up not only the treasures of classical Greek and Roman sculpture and architecture, but he also showed how the relation

between these classical forms were the expression of a kind of humanistic sensibility that had been lost. Greek art was seen as the embodiment of the whole man, of the realized, free and flourishing being. Early Romantics from Schiller and Hölderlin to Schlegel, among many others, began working our aesthetic theories as well as works of poetry that expressed the capacity of art to transform our senses and act as an alternative form of cognition. This became a central idea in the unfolding of the German aesthetic tradition: the notion that art can act as an alternative form of knowledge and has the power to alter our experience of reality. Art, for them was not only an expression of feeling, but it was, more importantly, a distinct form of cognition.

Nathan Ross’ excellent study raises this salient theme in German philosophy and its relevance for contemporary reflections on social criticism. His achievement is to provide a kind of connecting bridge between the Romantic poets and aestheticians of the late-eighteenth and earlynineteenth century with the critical theorists of the twentieth century. His basic thesis is that these two traditions are not in fact separate insofar as they both see the work of art as an object of our experience, as a means of communicating a kind of knowledge about the world. But it also acts, Ross argues, as a subject as well insofar as it acts to alter and interpret the world. The key idea here is that critical rationality requires an aesthetic component in the sense that it possesses the ability to elevate our sensibilities to the moral and political concerns as well. Not merely concerned with the question of “beauty,” the thinkers that Ross probes hold out for us the idea that art can reveal to us perversions within our social and moral world; they can make us sensitive to problems of injustice and to equip critical rationality with a weightier sensibility toward human development, flourishing and real freedom. In this sense, thinkers such as Benjamin and Adorno form a continuity with their Romantic predecessors in their attempt to show art’s power to transform what has become common to us: to bring to consciousness the real contradictions and experiences within modernity.

In his exploration of this unique tradition in aesthetic theory, Ross thereby raises for us a crucial problem that still dogs an ever-increasing technical civilization: how much our powers of rationality are still colonized by instrumental reason, how our moral and political ideas have been gutted of deeper questions about human freedom and the “good life,” and how we can call into question the pathologies of modernity that degrade the possibility for a humane culture and civilization. In a world of

vapid literature, regressed installations and painting, banal musical forms, and facile cinema, Ross’ study is perhaps needed now more than ever. Art seems to be losing its power to achieve precisely what the German Romantics and critical theorists believed it could: to serve as a means to intensify our sensitivity to the contradictions and pathologies of our time. Far from reminding us of the powers of humanism or the extent of our reification, contemporary art forms seem to reflect back to us a kind of absurdist capitulation to the status quo, expressing a kind of adolescent rebellion against what all seem to accept as unchangeable. In this sense, Ross’ reconstruction of the politics of aesthetic experience in German philosophy reminds us of the public purpose of aesthetics. We can therefore only profit from the ideas Ross highlights for us here and hope for a revival of art’s powers to educate and enlighten once again.

New York City Fall, 2016

a

This book has been a labor of love and, as such, the most difficult and costly type of project to pursue over many years. I feel truly fortunate to have had the conditions of concentrated leisure (what the Germans better call Musse) required to engage in deep readings and follow the connections that presented themselves as true to me.

I would like to thank most of all my wife, Sokthan, for helping me in the completion of the manuscript and for providing me with the solace needed over the years.

I would like to thank my colleague Scott Davidson for serving as a model of undaunted scholarly focus and for helping me in countless ways to protect the time needed to do scholarly work.

I first discovered the key figures in this study, Hölderlin and Benjamin, as an undergraduate, but it was only well after graduate school that I could see the unique depth and wisdom to these writers who stand somewhat outside the ordinary scope of philosophy. Thus I would like to think that the seed for this book was planted in Arcata and Bielefeld by an atmosphere of learning that allowed me to follow unfashionable or eccentric ideas to my heart’s content.

I would like to thank the many teachers and scholars who have guided me and influenced me over the years. Especially, Kay LaBahn for teaching me German and serving as a first guide into German literature; Elizabeth Millán for introducing me to the work of Schlegel; Georg Bertram for giving me contact to the still living and creative tradition of German aesthetic thought; and the many people with whom I have had conversations about these thinkers, including Bill Behun, Roger Foster, Stéfane Symons,

Marcia Morgan, Cat Moire, Corey McCall, and all of the contributors to my recent edited volume (whose voices I hope can be heard echoing in some of the later chapters).

In addition, I benefited greatly from getting to read and discuss many of the sections of this book at conferences such as the APA, SPEP, the North American Adorno Association, and the Rome Critical Theory Conference. I am grateful to have received detailed and valuable feedback at such conferences from Elizabeth Millán, Rocío Zambrana, Tom Huhn, Ben Crowe, and Eduardo Mendietta, among others. And finally, I owe a great thanks to Michael Thompson and Marcia Morgan for supporting this project.

2 Aesthetic Semblance and Play as Responses to the  Disfigurement of Human Social Existence in Schiller’s

Aesthetic Truth as the Mimesis of False Consciousness in Adorno’s

7 Conclusion: The Benjamin–Adorno Debate on the

a bbreviaT ions

AE Friedrich Schiller, Über die ӓsthetische Erziehung des Menschen (Stuttgart: Reclam, 2006)/Friedrich Schiller, On the Aesthetic Education of Man, trans. Reginald Snell (Mineola: Dover, 2004).

HW Friedrich Hölderlin, Sämtliche Werke, ed. D.E. Sattler (Frankfurt: Roter Stern, 1979).

KFSA Friedrich Schlgel, Kritische Friedrich Schlegel Ausgabe (KFSA), ed. Ernst Behler (Paderborn: Schöningh, 1958).

Origin Walter Benjamin, The Origin of German Tragic Drama, trans. John Osborne (London: Verso, 2003).

Pfau Friedrich Hölderlin, Essays and Letters on Theory, trans. Thomas Pfau (Albany: SUNY Press, 1988).

SW Walter Benjamin, Selected Works: Vol. 1–4, ed. Howard Eiland and Michael Jennings (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1996–2002).

Table 4.1 Approximation to Idea

CHAPTER 1

Introduction

This book develops a philosophy of aesthetic experience through the two philosophical movements that give it the greatest philosophical weight and social significance: early German Romanticism and early critical theory. In these two closely intertwined philosophical movements, aesthetic experience is not merely a passive response to art: it is an indispensable way to gain critical insight into the social and political context of our lives. Art is political for these thinkers not by painting a picture of political affairs, nor by formulating a message that has political impact, but even more in the modes of experience that it makes possible. It develops distinctive forms of experience that interact with and alter our conventional forms of experience. In doing so, it challenges us to see the world with new eyes, to question conceptions of knowledge and truth, and to explore new possibilities of praxis. In its critical relation to early and late capitalism, aesthetic experience challenges a worldview in which activity only matters when it serves an instrumental purpose, in which objects only matter when they have market value. It challenges this view of human activities and of objects by rehearsing a different model of activity and constructing other ways of viewing and interacting with objects. Ultimately, this book defends one of the most challenging and enigmatic claims of early critical theory: that art represents a form of truth. This claim represents a challenge not only to conventional approaches to art but even more to philosophical conceptions of truth and knowledge. Art’s truth content is experiential, and thus not translatable into a set of prosaic philosophical claims, but this does not

© The Author(s) 2017

N. Ross, The Philosophy and Politics of Aesthetic Experience, Political Philosophy and Public Purpose, DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-52304-0_1

mean that philosophy cannot confront and explain the distinctive ways in which art interacts with experience. What do these thinkers mean by aesthetic truth content? How do they define an authentic aesthetic experience? And, first, why consider early German Romanticism and Frankfurt school critical theory in their relationship to one another?

1 B enjamin ’ s D iscovery

At the beginning of his first book, The Concept of Critique in Early German Romanticism (1920), Walter Benjamin asserts that his work is not a study in the history of philosophy but in the history of a problem (Problemgeschichte).1 His distinction brings into relief some of the commitments that guide my own approach to the problem of aesthetic experience. With this distinction, Benjamin clarifies that he is not claiming to define the essence of Romanticism as a school of thought but rather showing the distinctive form that they give to the problem of criticism (Kritik). Conventionally, history of philosophy seeks to order thinkers into a narrative order by making different philosophies commensurate to each other, and it seeks to bring relevance to older forms of thought by translating them into the language and concerns of the present. By contrast, the problem-historical approach devised by Benjamin proceeds according to a slightly different method: it “blasts a specific era out of the homogenous course of history”2 and disrupts the idea that there is a continuity of thinking that makes up the history of philosophy by showing the creativity of thinkers in developing new problems. It looks at history not for answers to contemporary problems but for problems that estrange us from our way of thinking in productive ways. At the same time, Benjamin’s problemhistorical approach does not focus on isolating the work of great thinkers but rather focuses on the way philosophy happens in historical constellations. His study, like my own, reveals constellations of related solutions to the same problem that develop in and through dialogue between thinkers in close contact with one another. He shows how one thinker might devise a problem to be solved by another thinker, how an ambiguous, under-defined term in one thinker gets defined by another who was in correspondence. His method of scholarship constructs constellations around problems. In Benjamin’s study, the philosophy of Jena Romanticism is more than an aggregate of individual positions, but a constellation and a dialogue, and it also includes not just the circle of thinkers who actually identified with this term (Schlegel, Novalis) but also one on the periphery

who helped to develop some of its themes (Hölderlin). In my own examination of the Romantics, I will take a similar liberty in my use of the term ‘Romanticism’, which will be justified by a wealth of thematic and biographical connections.3 I thus use the term ‘Romanticism’ throughout this study loosely to describe a set of related positions developed by a group of thinkers who were in dialogue with each other in Jena during the 1790s. Each of these thinkers responds to the Kantian philosophy of cognition, freedom, and aesthetics with an original position that emphasizes the historical evolution of aesthetic forms and the power of art to liberate the mind for deeper and more critical forms of experience. Many contemporary approaches find new relevance and respectability in early German Romanticism by highlighting the epistemology or ethics of these thinkers and thus downplaying the view that they were ‘mere poets’4; while my study does not reject the view that these thinkers have highly developed conceptions of knowledge, ethics, and political agency, it feels no need to underplay the centrality that their writings clearly give to questions of presentation, form, and the meaning of art. By contrast, I argue that the problem of aesthetic experience is the key to unlocking the richness of their contributions to questions of epistemology and ethics.

Benjamin demonstrates that the Romantics arrive at a distinctive philosophy of criticism by changing the very problem under investigation. Unlike Kant, they do not understand critique as an inquiry into the powers of the subject that underlie given modes of experience. Unlike art critics of the modern era, they do not understand art criticism as a doctrine of taste or refined pleasure, a set of criteria for judging works.5 He notes how Romanticism breaks with the idea of the critic as an arbiter of taste. Rather, Benjamin shows that the Romantic philosophy of criticism relates critique to the power of artworks to reveal new ways of thinking about our relation to the world. Critique is an enquiry into the truth content of the artwork, where truth content entails the transformative impact of the work upon the subject.6 His work does not so much seek to make the Romantics answer to the problems of his own historical horizon but does something more daring: it seeks to highlight what is radical in the Romantic movement, what has not yet been digested because it does not stand in continuity with the framework of modern philosophy. In his philosophy of translation, he makes an analogous point about the purpose of translation: the best translation is not one that makes an ancient or foreign work easy to digest for modern readers but one that preserves its foreign quality in such a way as to alter our understanding of our own

language.7 It does not so much make Homer speak in German, as it leaves the German language transformed by its encounter with Homer. The same could be said of what distinguishes Problemgeschichte from the history of philosophy: his method makes the Romantics not more accessible or useful (as many contemporary accounts attempt) but more foreign and illuminating, with an ultimate view to the truth content of the problem in question.

It is fateful and worthy of deeper consideration that Benjamin’s first book, indeed, one of the earliest books in Frankfurt school critical theory, begins with an enquiry into the history of the ‘problem of critique’ in Jena Romanticism. As I will argue, Benjamin’s own critical theory depends in crucial ways on what he distills from the Romantic concept of critique. Both of these schools of thinking, at least up to a certain point in their developments, treat the problem of aesthetic experience as the central problem of philosophy, as a kind of touchstone for asking questions about knowledge, truth, and social critique. The present study does not attempt a comprehensive history of German aesthetic thinking or a comprehensive history of the concept of aesthetic experience. Rather, it seeks to investigate the special affinity of these two philosophical movements in their unique definition of the problem of how aesthetic experience relates to social critique. They understand aesthetic experience as a unique mode of human activity, one that does not seek to know the world in a literal, factual sense, or answer to the demands of economic exchange. Ultimately, I argue that they converge in the view that aesthetic experience represents a crucial mode of truth, that is, a unique and indispensable way of gaining critical insight into the social and cultural space that surrounds us.

The problem of aesthetic experience does not overlap exactly with the more prevalent contemporary problem of defining art, although it intersects with it in crucial ways. The effort to define art seeks to provide a conceptual definition we could use to discern what is art and what is not. There have been efforts to develop a theory of aesthetic experience that would answer the problem of defining art: we might define art by defining the kind of experience it incites.8 This book does not pose the problem in this way for a number of reasons. First, an aesthetic experience is not necessarily an experience of an artwork. It is equally possible, and perhaps even more valuable, to have an aesthetic experience of nature. Secondly, it is not clear that all artworks are constituted primarily as objects meant for aesthetic experience.9 I would not want to say that such works are not ‘real’ artworks because they do not fit with a certain definition of aesthetic

experience. But nor would I want to say that the notion of aesthetic experience developed by thinkers from Schiller to Adorno is philosophically invalidated by artistic developments that do not fit with their theory. Instead of a means of distinguishing art from non-art, I argue that the aesthetic philosophies within these two schools of thought pose a different problem: to define the purpose and value of aesthetic experience, including an aesthetic relation to nature, as a vital and irreplaceable form of social critique. In recognizing that their problem is not the same as our problem of defining art, we gain a kind of entry into a different horizon of thought. What is this problem?

2 a esthetic e xperience as a p hilosophical p ro Blem

Aesthetic experience is not merely the way in which a subject responds to a work of art or any other object with aesthetic properties. Even more, aesthetic experience can be used to describe the way in which an artwork contains an experience of reality. The artwork is potentially both an object of experience, among others, as well as a subject, that is, a point at which the world is reflected. Aesthetic experience describes not only the way in which we see art but also the unique way in which art responds to the world.

Following this insight, the thinkers in this study are not primarily interested in a theory of taste or beauty. For the aesthetic thinkers of the time of the enlightenment, culminating in Kant, the primary question that aesthetic experience posed to philosophy was: how do we define and arbitrate our claims of taste? Is beauty just like any other form of pleasing experience, or does it rest on some certain definite rules or principles? These questions concerning taste and beauty lead Immanuel Kant to formulate one of the most brilliant and influential works of aesthetic philosophy, The Critique of the Power of Judgment (1790). In it, he defines beauty through the power of the mind to engage with the form of objects in a way that is neither knowledge nor interest. Some objects appear to have a form that enables a ‘free play’ of the same powers that we use in cognition, imagination, and understanding but in a way that leads not to any specific cognition but to a disinterested pleasure. To engage with the world as a free play of appearance and judge the aesthetic quality of these appearances represents an important third capacity of the human mind for Kant, one which demonstrates our ability to agree with each other even when we

cannot explain our experience in concepts. Hannah Arendt even argues that Kant’s definition of aesthetic judgment hints at the critique of politics that Kant never wrote, since it shows his belief in a kind of pre-conceptual capacity for human judgment and agreement, a kind of sensus communis that could perhaps underlie our political experience.10 Kant is undoubtedly one of the first great philosophers of aesthetic experience, but his work remains outside of the problematic of this study in a crucial sense.

All of the thinkers in this study are influenced by Kant’s Critique of the Powers of Judgment in decisive ways, and yet they are fundamentally concerned with a different problem than the problem of taste. Kant’s account of aesthetic experience departs from a problem that belonged to the Enlightenment: can we define beauty? Can we say what makes certain objects beautiful? And he resolved this problem through the methods of transcendental philosophy: he showed that beauty is not so much a quality of the object that has determinate properties that make it beautiful but rather that the possibility of beauty as a common human experience points toward a capacity of the human mind, a free interaction of the powers of the human mind.11 The post-Kantians thinkers in this study approach art and the aesthetic in a very different way. Their notion of the aesthetic is not guided by beauty, by refined pleasure, nor even by the experience of the sublime. Rather, they are primarily interested in the power of art and the aesthetic to heighten our capacity for criticism, to educate us to perceive injustice and untruth, and to respond to these in creative ways. In Benjamin’s study of the Romantics, he attributes to them a shift in aesthetic thinking that he calls ‘the retreat of the beautiful’.12 By this he means that the Romantics look to art as a space for an experience that is not harmonious and pleasurable but rather enigmatic, troubling, and yet also educational. Benjamin and Adorno re-conceptualize this transformation in the function of aesthetic experience as a question of truth content Adorno writes, in a formulation that guides his great, fragmentary masterpiece, Aesthetic Theory (1970): “All aesthetic questions terminate in those of the truth content of the works: is the spirit that a specific work objectively bears in its form true?”13

I believe that many accounts of the role of art in early critical theory underemphasize or reject the theme of truth content at their peril. To be sure, this is one of the themes that is hardest to define in a way that does not challenge conventional boundaries between philosophical subdisciplines.14 And yet if we do not take the ideal of aesthetic truth content seriously, we lose view of the positive import of the theme of aesthetic

experience and end up with a philosophy of aesthetic negativity. That is, we end up with a view of art that is purely irrational, negative, destructive, or otherwise outside the bounds of explanation.15 In these negative accounts, we get a view of how art is ‘other’ but not an answer as to why this otherness matters. Put another way, the notion of aesthetic education becomes indeterminate and without any direction if this education is not guided by some emphatic ideal, some critical distinction between truth and falsity. My own effort to define the theme of aesthetic truth will work backwards from Adorno’s, sometimes enigmatic, pronouncements to discover a common pattern that animates the various philosophies of aesthetic experience.

3 t ruth c ontent

The authentic experience of the artwork is not the one that judges it according to standards of refined taste, but rather an approach of engagement with the work on its own terms, immanent critique that enters into the artwork on its own terms in order to learn something. This process of education and critique ultimately has its value in terms of a relative advance in truth content. One of the central and most difficult scholarly goals of this book is to define the notion of aesthetic truth content that operates as the central programmatic goal in early critical theory. The notion of aesthetic truth content represents not only a challenge to the older notion of aesthetic taste, but rather even more an on-going challenge to philosophy itself. To this day, it has proven challenging for scholars of critical theory to understand and accept the theme of aesthetic truth content that plays a key role in the thought of Adorno and Benjamin. Truth seems to belong to thoughts, judgments, propositions, and to scientific and philosophical claims. Truth seems to be a category of inquiry for philosophical epistemology, or perhaps for the ethics of communication, but not for aesthetics, which deals with a set of experiences that seem to elude conceptual articulation. Some of the best known efforts to place Adorno’s Aesthetic Theory into a broader philosophical context have challenged or rejected his notion of truth content.16 While Adorno’s notion of aesthetic truth is enigmatic when taken on its own terms, I argue in this book that it gains clarity when placed into a constellation with the work of Benjamin and the post-Kantian tradition.

It might seem that the only way to make sense of the idea of aesthetic truth is to place art into a kind of analogy with other kinds of things that we recognize to be true, such as judgments or propositions. As I will

argue, the thinkers in his study take the opposite approach. That is, they seek to develop a theory of how art makes possible a distinctive kind of truth content that does not resemble discursive knowledge. In developing an account of aesthetic experience, they consider its transformational impacts on the subject. Not: how does it please us? But: how does it change the way in which we think and feel? And how might this transformation represent an experience of truth?

This book does not develop one single definition of aesthetic truth content, but five different accounts of aesthetic truth content, each mediated through the problem of aesthetic experience. However, there is a basic pattern that emerges in Schiller and holds for each of the subsequent thinkers, especially Adorno: Art has truth content to the extent that it enables a form of experience that negates or undoes certain social pathologies prevalent to modern culture. This means that their theories of aesthetic experience stand in a dependent and determinately negative relation to specific critical claims about modern culture. It remains impossible to grasp the key term in their aesthetic philosophies without also examining their social philosophies. This basic pattern will take a different form in each thinker: Schiller develops a general critique of the division of labor in industrial society, as well as a critique of the modern forms of knowledge that isolate sense intuition from conceptual understanding. Benjamin formulates a critique of late capitalism as a religion that instills itself in our subjectivity and robs us of the very capacity for experience. Adorno famously offers a scathing critique of modern civilization that focuses on the link between enlightenment and delusion, between the effort to overcome mythology and the promotion of totalitarian form of reductionism. In each case, we will see that the way in which they conceptualize the potential truth content of art rests on making explicit the structure of their social critique, so as to grasp its relation to the experiential content of art forms. A prominent metaphor will be that of immunization: art is an antidote that immunizes. In order for the antidote to work, it must in a sense encompass the nature of the illness. Aesthetic theory needs social critique in order to grasp what would represent a relative advance of truth content.

There has been a tendency on the part of scholars to separate the aesthetic thought of critical theory from the nitty-gritty details of their social critique.17 These scholars have the view that an aesthetic theory must be able to stand on its own, without depending on the politics of these thinkers. These scholars find the politics of the Frankfurt school to be an exaggerated product of their time, while an aesthetic theory has the responsibility to be more abstract, to apply to art in a more general sense.

In my view, this approach makes their aesthetic theories too abstract, but it also does too little justice to the far ranging consequences of their social critiques. One of the things that Adorno most respects in the work of his friend Benjamin is his ability to read philosophically decisive themes into the most fleeting, seemingly ephemeral social trends.18 My general approach in this text is to read the thinkers in this study both as theorists of aesthetic experience and as critics of modern society, so as to demonstrate the mutual dependence of these themes. The thinkers of Jena Romanticism and early critical theory are not so much political philosophers in the sense of developing an overall theory of political normativity or ideal institutions; rather, they are social critics in the sense of responding to the direction in which they see their culture developing. However, they embed their social criticism in an overall account of modernity, the nature of historical development and the changing relation between the subject and the object of experience. In this sense, their social critiques have both relevance to a particular historical context and on-going philosophical relevance to those of us who come later. The Romantics and critical theorists share a skepticism about the Enlightenment idea of progress, not because they place unquestioned value on past, traditional forms of society, but because they believe that progress that is not submitted to close critical scrutiny will lead to the proliferation of injustices. In short, the critical theorists and the early Romantics share on overall sympathy with the emancipatory goals of the enlightenment, but they also believe that true human emancipation has not yet been made possible.19 Their critique of modernity is inextricably bound up with a critique of the role of capitalism in modernity: in capitalism, progress is present as growth of wealth or growth of market forces that generally stand in an inverse relation to the real development of human needs. As Schiller writes of the progress of the division of labor in early capitalism, “[o]ne-sidedness in the exercise of powers leads the individual inevitably to error, but the species to truth”.20 As he argues, it is precisely those features of the modern worldview that allow us to gain greater wealth and deeper knowledge that also make us individually incapable of having a comprehensive, meaningful experience of the overall context of our lives. Schiller’s line of thought establishes a critique of progress that is essentially a critique of the effect of progress upon the concrete, lived experience of the individual. The goal of the critique is not to undo the economic and scientific progress of modernity by fleeing into some pre-modern primitive experience, but to recover an awareness of the subjective resources for experience that are stifled by the force of progress. How can we gain an awareness of the limitations

inherent in the one-sided progression of instrumental and scientific models of subjectivity, without falling into some kind of pre-modern, mythic worldview? This is where art plays a crucial role in relation to experience. My thesis is: aesthetic truth is the experiential negativity of some kind of social falsehood or pathology. This approach stands in a symmetrical pattern to a well-known approach in contemporary critical theory: aesthetics of negativity. Christoph Menke develops an influential conception of aesthetic negativity, using the theories of Adorno and Derrida as his model. In his account, art involves an experience of the breakdown or frustration of our ordinary, rational ways of making sense of the world.21 But Menke’s notion of aesthetic negativity is not the same as a theory of aesthetic truth; indeed, he seems to avoid adopting this notion from Adorno. In contrast to Menke’s notion of aesthetic negativity, my account of aesthetic truth entails rescuing some emphatic, positive content from a determinate negation. Menke’s theory of aesthetic negativity makes the aesthetic into something other and different, a negation of reason. By contrast, my approach demonstrates that aesthetic truth actively negates patterns of seeing the world that are false, problematic or delusional.

A certain complexity will become clear in the relationship between aesthetic experience and social critique throughout the chapters. In the chapters on Schiller and Adorno, I present their social critiques and then present their accounts of aesthetic experience as a response to their critiques. But in the chapters on Hölderlin and Schlegel, a more compelling and integral relationship will emerge: they conceptualize aesthetic experience not as the solution to a given problem, but as the ground for a critique of society. Hölderlin and Schlegel do not develop a critique of society in prosaic terms, and then look to poetry for a solution. Rather, they develop methods of knowledge and thinking that are inherently aesthetic. They make clear that aesthetic experience is a mode of critical knowledge that entails an altered relationship between object and subject. To frame the matter in another way: aesthetic experience is not merely a different way of experiencing the world, but an experience that leads to a different relationship with the world.

4 e xperience

It will not be possible to develop a philosophy of aesthetic experience without focusing on the relatively complex and idiosyncratic way in which the philosophers in this study understand the notion of experience. In

much of modern philosophy, experience is simply defined as anything that happens to a subject of which it is aware, or as the initial raw material of cognition that we take in from the senses. Perhaps more than any thinker in this study, Walter Benjamin is aware of the need to develop a new, richer concept of experience (Erfahrung), not only as a corrective to the philosophy of his time, but as a way of establishing a philosophical foundation for social critique.

In his early work, Benjamin argues that modern and especially neoKantian philosophies have missed something important by equating experience with sense data or with the raw material that we interpret in cognition.22 In his view, the prevalent notion of experience reduces the object to a minimum, to a pure thing, a unit of data, which can be ordered and controlled by scientific consciousness. The problem that he sees in this notion of experience is that it conceals the historically and culturally mediated nature of the relation between subject and object, the way in which our paradigm filters the material of experience, and he believes that a true notion of experience would have to restore the “metaphysical neutrality of subject and object”.23 Additionally, the reductive notion of experience robs philosophy of the ability to distinguish the meaning of different modes of consciousness. On the basis of this early program, Benjamin turns toward the perspective of children, the mentally ill and artists to discover some elements of experience that seems eliminated in the modern concept. Increasingly in his work, the concept of experience becomes a placeholder for something that is lost or stifled by oppressive features of modern life.24 Indeed, he seems more concerned with diagnosing the loss of experience than with providing a definition of the concept itself. Nevertheless, behind all of his mobile thoughts is the notion that having an experience would be something extraordinary, rather than ordinary, a capacity for critical awareness that responds to the world, rather than molding it to the needs of the subject.

In order to understand how the problem of experience connects early critical theory with the Jena Romantic philosophy, it is necessary to look not only at the power that each movement gives to art, but at the way in which they seek to recover the concept of experience from a predominantly epistemological and cognitive context. Indeed, it is Benjamin’s initial dissatisfaction with Kant and his program to recover the notion of experience that initially drives him to study the Romantics and to treat their notion of art criticism as an epistemologically crucial category. If the enlightenment notion of experience essentially revolves around the subject

encountering the object as a pure x, a definable entity, then we could say that the Romantic notion of experience, according to Benjamin’s own interpretation, revolves around the subject finding the object to be a subject in its own right. Writing of the Romantics, Benjamin argues “the thing, to the extent that it intensifies reflection in itself and includes other beings in its self-knowledge, radiates its self-knowledge onto these other beings”.25 While Benjamin criticizes Kant for relying on a concept of experience that reduces the object to a nadir, he finds the Romantic epistemology rests on a quite different metaphysical foundation that will lead to a richer philosophy of experience. What speaks to Benjamin most of all out of the Romantics is a certain kind of living, reflective, non-instrumental and noncognitive encounter between the subject and the object.

Increasingly, Benjamin conceptualizes this living and dynamic relation in his own thinking as a matter of mimesis. The subject has a capacity to make itself similar to the object. This capacity allows the subject to make the object into something living that speaks to it. The mimetic element describes a key dimension of what it means to have an experience. Benjamin comes close to offering a clear definition of experience in a fragment:

Experiences (Erfahrungen) are lived similarities. There is no greater error than to construe experience … according to the model on which the exact natural sciences are based. What is decisive here is not the causal connections established over time, but the similarities that have been lived.

Most people have no wish to learn by experience. Moreover, their convictions prevent them from doing so.26

Elsewhere, Benjamin defines mimesis itself as the capacity for recognizing and responding to similarities: seeing one thing as a microcosm or macrocosm of another, recognizing a foreign word as meaning the same thing as a word from a known language.27 In each case, we see something important about how Benjamin frames the true experience: it is an ability to learn from what has happened, in the sense of discovering a pattern in things that one can reproduce in another context. It is not simply a matter of taking in data, of acquiring information, or of allowing something to enter one’s field of awareness. One could see or hear many artworks without having an experience. One can look up the meaning of a word in a dictionary, and yet be incapable of using the word to think

something inventive or insightful. Rather, experience comes to fruition at the moment in which a pattern emerges that allows the subject to mime, to duplicate, to express, and to respond to what is subjective in the object.

This passage also reveals something essential about the theme of experience in Benjamin: that it is a capacity that cannot be taken for granted, indeed, that it can be lost or threatened. It is possible to move through the world, to participate in it, without having an experience of it. In the above quote, the enemy of experience is conviction. The person who is convinced has no faculty for experience, because a conviction prevents one from recognizing a deeper pattern of affinity in things. In other texts Benjamin would meditate more profoundly on the loss of the very capacity to have experience. He writes of the years during and after the World War I: “Never has experience been contradicted more thoroughly: strategic experience has been contravened by positional warfare; economic experience, by inflation; physical experience, by hunger; moral experience, by the ruling powers”.28 He concludes that there is no storyteller who could do justice to this time, because the very capacity to have true experience had withered under this stifling combination of physical, economic and political circumstances that elude experience. By this point, Benjamin thinks of experience as a placeholder for a lost capacity to respond in a human and critical way to events that seem beyond control. As I will argue, Benjamin’s view of art is shaped by his thesis on the loss of experience in crucial ways. He charges art not so much with the task of recovering our capacity for experience, but rather with the task of taking into itself the very power that robs us of the capacity for experience. For Benjamin, it is not a matter of simply recovering a lost capacity, but of immunizing ourselves against the power that robs us of this capacity.

At first it might seem as if aesthetic experience is simply a species of experience, one kind of experience among others. In a sense this is correct. But the relation between aesthetic experience and experience in general is made more complicated by the thesis on the loss of experience. Aesthetic experience is not merely one species of experience, but it is also a key to the recovery of the concept of experience in its entirety. This is because the artwork is not only something that one might experience, an object among others, but also an objectification of experience, in the sense described above. Put another way, the artwork is both a product and a trigger of mimesis. It is a product of the very kind of capacity for recognizing and responding to lived similarities through which Benjamin defines experience, and yet it also demands a mode of comportment that

is fundamentally mimetic in order to be recognized. Following Benjamin’s challenging thesis on the loss of experience, Adorno argues that the artwork represents a site at which to recover experience from the context that threatens it.29 Adorno responds to Benjamin’s enigmatic thesis on the loss of experience by calling the artwork a refuge of mimesis30: a site at which we experience something of what we are blocked from experiencing. “Art is a mimetic mode of behavior (Verhalten) that is held onto, that is preserved, even in an epoch of rationality”.31 The artwork is not merely an object or a domain of experience, but rather it is itself an embodiment of experience in such a way as to reveal or critique what leads to the loss of experience.

Aesthetic experience thus entails two distinctive, but related relationships involving the artwork: it describes both the response of a subject to an artwork, as well as the relation of the artwork to the world. We experience the artwork as an artwork when we experience it aesthetically; but also, the artwork is the objectification of an aesthetic experience. As John Dewey notes in his book, Art and Experience, the artist does not create independently from how the spectator receives the work, but creates a work in such a way that she constantly checks and adjusts it according to how it is experienced.32 Aesthetic experience thus does not simply describe the attitude of the spectator who passively receives an artwork. Rather, it describes the attitude or mode of awareness that guides both its creation and its interpretation. In Benjamin’s view, which he acquires from the Romantics, criticism is not merely a receptive state of mind but a moment in the on-going life of the work. As Benjamin writes of the Romantic notion of criticism, “It (criticism) belongs to the meaning of the work itself … For the Romantics, criticism is far less the judgment of the work, and far more the method of its consummation”.33 What he says here of criticism is true of aesthetic experience in a more general sense: it is not just a passive or discerning act in relation to its object, but the activity, the mode of comportment that is internal to the work.

This dual relation of aesthetic experience, as both a relation to the artwork and a relation of the artwork to the world, explains how art is socially and politically relevant to these thinkers. Adorno and Benjamin use the notion of monad to describe this paradoxical dual relation of art to reality34: the artwork is both a relatively autonomous, isolated structure that demands to be grasped on its own terms, but at the same time, this monad contains within its own order a reflection of everything else that is outside of it. Art is a monad in that it is both relatively autonomous and

socially relevant. Art is relatively autonomous in a few different senses: first, any effort to translate the meaning of an artwork into a ‘message’ that could be formulated separately will miss something about the experience. Secondly, the artwork is successful to the extent that it is relatively autonomous from demands of the market place or from rules of social conduct, and formed according to demands of aesthetic experience. But at the same time their theories of art are constantly political: they believe that it is precisely when we perceive art in an aesthetic way that it teaches us most about the critique of social conditions. Another way of articulating this notion of aesthetic autonomy is to say that aesthetic experience is always both inside and outside the work35: it is both an immanent critique, which takes the work on its own terms, and it is a socially reflective critique, in that it considers what the experience that emerges from the artwork teaches us about our state of culture.

5 c apitalism an D the l oss of e xperience

I have argued up to this point that aesthetic experience offers truth content to the extent that it critiques certain prevalent pathologies created by modern society. But this remains too abstract and politically neutral: to be specific, aesthetic experience stands in a critical relation to capitalism. But how does the theme of aesthetic experience reveal a critique of capitalism? Is it not a matter of what specific artworks have to say, rather than the form of aesthetic experience itself?

The relation of art to the loss of experience, as well as the relation of the loss of experience to capitalism, can perhaps best be illustrated by the way in which the critical theorists adopt and enrich Marx’s thesis on the fetishism of commodities. As Marx argues at the outset of Capital, commodity production involves not only the production of a thing that satisfies a human desire, but also the production of a mystifying illusion about the world in which we live. As soon as the commodity is in the marketplace, we see it as a thing that bears value in comparison to other things, rather than as a result of a complex social relationship between producers, capitalists and consumers. The commodity makes us forget the very social fabric to which we belong and out of which it gets its value. Marx calls this the “religious reflex” within capitalism.36 This illusion is what allows us to ignore the way in which market behavior entails participation in oppression, and it makes the market seem like a quasi-natural, value neutral arrangement of human behavior. Marx places his section on the

Another random document with no related content on Scribd:

address is worth remembering always, he must recite it several times during the next week, and go over it again next month, next term, and next year. There will come a time, depending upon his native retentiveness and upon his method of memorizing, when it will no longer be necessary to repeat it for the sake of fixing the address in memory. It will not take a great deal of time to recall that which we believe we have fixed permanently last week or last month, and by doing this we shall add greatly to the probability of possible recall a year or ten years from now, and incidentally discover, much to our surprise, how much has already escaped.

Teachers often unconsciously follow the cramming method in their attempt to have children advance rapidly; and, as is always the case when this method is employed, what has apparently been learned is soon forgotten. Fortunately for all concerned, many of the responses which need to be reduced to an automatic basis are demanded over and over again as the child progresses from grade to grade, and are thus provided for. But much that is now lost could be retained, and each succeeding teacher could accomplish more than is now customary, if only this principle of habit formation were commonly observed.

In the case of a series of responses to be made automatic, be careful to include each member of the series: Much of our work is weak because it lacks system. If we are engaged in teaching addition combinations, we should be absolutely certain that we have taught every possible combination. If we want to be sure that children know how to write numbers up to one million, we must have given them drill on all of the possible difficulties. If children are always to respond correctly when problems involving two steps in reasoning are presented, we must have been careful to provide for the purpose of drill all of the combinations of situations involving addition, multiplication, subtraction, and division which can occur. For any other similar field, the same care must be exercised.

The greater part of the time should be spent in drilling upon that part of the work which presents special difficulty. There is no use in spending one’s time equally on all of the words included in any list. Some of them can probably be spelled with little or no drill, while

others may require very careful study and many repetitions. In any other field the same situation will be found. Many of the responses desired will be reduced to the basis of habit readily, and a few will require continued attention. It is the function of the teacher to discover these special difficulties as soon as possible, to clear up any obscurity in ideas which may stand in the way, and then to drill with special reference to these special cases.

Briefly summarized, it is the function of the teacher in guiding pupils in the formation of habits to see to it that they have the correct idea of the thing to be done; to secure the maximum of motive and to maintain the maximum of attention during the process; to guard against carelessness and lapses by insisting upon the accuracy or the adequacy of the responses; to provide occasion for repetitions from time to time with gradually lengthened intervals; to be careful not to omit any of a group or series of responses equally important; to spend the greater part of the time and energy of both herself and pupils upon those cases which present special difficulty.

F C R

W. C. Bagley, The Educative Process, Chapter XXII.

S. H. Rowe, Habit Formation and the Science of Teaching, Chapter XIII. Exercises.

1. Name the subjects or parts of subjects in which drill work is essential.

2. What was there of value in the old-fashioned method of choosing sides and “spelling down”?

3. Name some of the devices which you have used in drill work, and justify their use.

4 What argument can you advance for postponing the beginning of writing lessons until the middle of the first year or later?

5. Which would be better: to present the multiplication table in regular series (3 × 1 = 3; 3 × 2 = 6; 3 × 3 = 9, etc.), or in some other order? (3 × 5 = 15; 3 × 2 = 6; 3 × 7 = 21; 3 × 4 = 12, etc.)

6 If a boy was writing a composition and wanted to use a word that he did not know how to spell, what would you expect him to do?

7. What are the objections to learning rules of spelling?

8 In a drill lesson in arithmetic, which would you consider the better: to have the children work as individuals for the highest score, or to divide them into groups and have one group try to do better than the other?

9 Criticize the following lesson, as a fourth-grade exercise in spelling The teacher placed the following list of words on the board, and told the pupils to study them believe conduct have forget agriculture manufacture store plow wagon cultivate harness exports crops dairy freight drought fertilizer transport depot wheat

10 A teacher who spent a large part of her time having the class recite the multiplication tables in concert was distressed to find that a majority of the class did not know the tables when examination time came What was the explanation?

11. In a school where the children had a forty-minute period for a writing lesson, the results during the last ten minutes were invariably poorer than during the first quarter of the period. How could you hope to change the result?

12. In some schools the teachers always spend two weeks before the examination period in review of the term’s work. Why are such reviews necessary in some cases, while children do just as well in examinations in other schools which do not have this review period?

13 A teacher taught children that they could always tell how much nine times any number was by subtracting one from that number for the tens place, then adding a number which will make nine for the units place (e g 5 × 9 = ? 5 - 1 = 4 (tens); 4 + 5 = 9 ∴ 5 is the number of units, and 5 × 9 = 45) Is this a good way to teach this table?

14. How can you know when it is wise to discontinue drill work?

15. Do you think it necessary to plan for a drill lesson?

16. Could you plan your work so that your pupils will know at the end of the year all of the poems you have taught during the previous eight or ten months?

CHAPTER V

We are skeptical to-day of that sort of teaching which aims mainly to equip children with a body of accepted knowledge in order that they may some time find use for this body of information in later life. We emphasize, rather, the control of mental activity which makes for the discovery of truth and the avoidance of error. Thinking of this sort is purposeful. We control or direct our ideas toward some end, toward the solution of some problem. One great purpose of teaching must be to provide the opportunity and the stimulus for this kind of thinking. We may not be able to lay down any fixed order of procedure, nor to devise any set of rules whereby children may be trained to be good reasoners; but we can consider what is involved in the process, point out the possibilities of interference, and suggest some of the means to be employed in encouraging this type of mental activity on the part of children. In this chapter we shall confine ourselves to that type of reasoning which we call inductive. This type of schoolroom exercise has usually been treated as composed of five steps; namely, preparation, presentation, comparison and abstraction, generalization, and application. We shall employ this classification to guide us in our discussion of the process.

Preparation: To prepare a child to reason in a given situation from the data in hand to the conclusions which must of necessity follow, it is first of all necessary that he should see that the situation presents a problem. We reason only when we have some aim or purpose which can be satisfied by the process. But if consciousness of aim or problem is at the foundation of this type of thinking, and if we are to

deal with children in groups, it is essential that the situation which involves the problem be made the common possession of all. The step of preparation presents these two problems to the teacher: (1) to find a basis in experience already had, or to provide the experience which involves the problem to be considered; (2) to make the children feel the necessity for the solution, i.e. to make the problem vital to them.

In considering the necessity for common experience as a basis for discovering the problem to children, we are dealing with the principle of apperception. Briefly stated, it is this,—that any object or situation has meaning for us only as it connects itself with and is interpreted by our previous experience. Suppose, for example, that a group of first-grade children were asked to tell what made seeds grow. It is possible that some of them would not know, could not interpret from past experience, the meaning of seeds. If the class were at work in a large city, we could be sure that many had never been conscious that growing plants had any connection with seeds, and there would be few, if any, who had ever noticed the conditions under which such growth takes place. The first problem for the teacher in this case would be solved only when, through recall of past experiences, observations, or experiments, the experience “seeds growing” became the common possession of the group. This is an extreme case, one in which the experience which involves the problem is entirely wanting. At the other end of the series, we may have a problem for consideration, the basis for which is found in experiences common to all children. But even though this be the case, there will still be need for the recall of the experience and for making prominent some factor heretofore unnoticed before the children will be ready to reason. We may suppose that all children have had experience with streets or roads, but we shall want to recall many of these experiences in order to make significant the problem of transportation which we wish to consider in the class in home geography.

The step of preparation has only partially accomplished its purpose when the experience necessary to the realization of the problem has been recalled or provided. Still greater skill is required

in making the child conscious of the problem. Indeed, it may well be argued that in the curriculum as it is at present organized, very many of the problems that we ask children to solve are problems for them only because we, as teachers, require that that certain piece of work be done. Often the child’s problem consists mainly in avoiding, as far as possible, the work which we require, which has little or no significance for him. Children would do much more thinking if we were only more careful to give them childish problems to solve. Too frequently the organization of knowledge which we impose is influenced exclusively by our adult logical conceptions. Not that children should be illogical, but rather that child logic and the child’s ability to reason depend upon his ability to appreciate problems, upon his experience, and upon his ability to interpret that experience. When we impose our adult point of view upon him, when we ask him to take our problem and with the data that we supply ask him to work out our solution, whatever else may be said of the exercise, it may not be called an exercise in reasoning by children.

If we do respect the child’s experience and point of view, the task still remains of making all of the group of children we teach conscious of the aim as their problem. There is no greater test of teaching skill than this. Can the teacher, after having brought to mind the experiences which are relevant to the work she wishes the children to do, make them conscious of a lack in this experience; can she awaken the need for further consideration of past experience and a desire to reconstruct and to amplify it? In proportion as she is able to accomplish this result, we may be sure that children are reasoning upon problems which are vital to them, and that the motive has been provided which will secure the maximum of controlled intellectual activity on their part. The best single test of the accomplishment of this ideal is to require that the statement of aim be made by the children themselves as a result of the guidance we have given. This conception of the meaning and significance of the aim suggests the solution of the difficulty which some people find in harmonizing the idea of instruction with the doctrine of self-activity.

Instruction, when properly conducted, does not impose the ideas, the problems, or the conclusions of adults upon children. Rather we

are concerned in instruction with the child’s experience, his tendency to react, his need of adjustment; and our function as teachers is to guide him, to stimulate him to his own best efforts, to insure the maximum of self-activity while we guide this activity toward the accomplishment of ends which are desirable. The difficulty is, of course, that the problem for solution at any given time may not be equally vital to every member of the group. Here is where the element of control enters somewhat in opposition to the self-activity of the individual. But this condition of affairs is necessarily true both in school and out of it, for society sets up for us certain norms or standards of experience which must be realized by all, and we must for the sake of economy handle children in groups. If the problem is not beyond the child’s comprehension, if it deals with situations which are significant to him, if the solution derived has some bearing on his future action, if he has carefully scrutinized his experience in the light of the problem stated and has brought to bear those elements which are significant for its solution, we may be confident that the activity resulting is closely akin to that which is found in the controlled thinking of men the world over.

In order that it may be more easy for children to focus their attention upon the problem in hand, there is considerable advantage in a clear, concise, concrete, and preferably a brief statement of the aim.[7] A problem is half solved when one can state it clearly. So long as the problem is not sufficiently well defined to admit of accurate statement on the part of pupils, there is danger that there may be much wandering in its consideration. One of the great lessons to be taught in work of this sort is the need of examining the ideas as they suggest themselves to see whether or not they are relevant.

The argument as it has been stated above points to the statement of aim as the culmination of the step of preparation. This does not mean that a considerable period must always elapse in the conduct of an exercise of this type before the aim can be stated. There are occasions, and when the teaching has been good they should be frequent, when the lesson should begin with the statement of the problem discovered in a previous lesson and made clear in the assignment of work. In other cases the same aim may hold for

several days; i.e. until the problem is solved In general, as we advance through the grades, the ends for which children work should become relatively more remote, and the achievement of these ends should require a longer period of work. There is an advantage in setting up subsidiary aims which will make steps of progress in the realization of the larger purpose.

Another distinction that it is well to keep in mind concerns the development of intellectual interests on the part of children. The characteristic aim for a first-grade child may make its appeal chiefly to his desire for satisfaction, which has little intellectual significance; but education fails if it does not make for an increase of interest in intellectual activity. For example, a first-grade boy may be led to count because he wants to be able to tell how many marbles he has, or how to measure the materials he uses in constructive work; while the mathematician may work night and day upon a problem of mathematics because of a purely speculative interest in the result. We may not hope to produce the great mathematician in the elementary school, but we may hope after a certain point has been reached in our study of arithmetic that a boy will recognize the necessity for drill in addition simply because he realizes that in the ordinary affairs of life this knowledge is required.

Presentation: The full realization of the problem to be solved involves a consideration of data already at hand in experience. When we have the problem clearly in mind, we examine this experience more carefully to see what bearing it may have upon the solution, or we gather further data, observe more critically or more extensively, or experiment in such a manner as to involve the solution of our problem. What is the function of the teacher during this part of the process? There is no single answer to this question. Sometimes the work of the teacher will consist almost wholly in helping children to recall their past experience and to apply it to the question at hand. At another time, when experience is lacking, the teacher must direct children to the sources of data, guide them in their observations or experiments, or even give them outright all of the data that she can bring to bear on the situation. It will not always be economical to wait for children to gather the data for themselves,

just as it is not always feasible to require them to reach conclusions for themselves. There are times when the best teaching consists in demonstration, and occasions arise when the only feasible course for the teacher is to literally flood the children with data from which they may draw their conclusions.

Again the problem of gathering data becomes the problem of memory. We want children to think, and we should insist that they gather facts with reference to the solution of some problem; but the solution may not always be immediate. We may suspend judgment while we gather further facts and organize them. The facts gathered for one purpose, when rearranged with reference to a new problem, take on a new meaning. If this be true, we may not in our zeal for clear thinking neglect the tools with which we work. There may be some people who have a great many facts and who reason little, but no one can reason without data. Our ability to think logically upon any topic is conditioned by our ability to see facts in new relations, to reorganize our data with reference to new problems; but facts we must have, and a memory stored with facts is one of the greatest aids to thinking.

One of the means mentioned above for the gathering of data was observation. It is necessary that we appreciate the fact that observation involves something more than having the thing present to the senses. Our observations are significant for our thinking when we have clearly in view the problem which the observations are to help solve. Teachers sometimes make the mistake of supposing that when children have objects with which to work they have a problem. It is not unusual to hear teachers speak of objective work as concrete work Now the concreteness of a situation is not at all dependent upon the presence of objects. Logically a situation may be concrete, and yet present no objects to the senses. On the other hand, objects may be present, children may be directed to use them, and yet in the absence of any real problem the work done may be of the most abstract sort. Objects help to make a situation concrete when the problem under consideration demands their presence, or when they help to make clear the situation under consideration. For example, children may have peas or beans in solving problems in

addition; they serve to present objectively the reality which is symbolized by the teacher or pupils in their written work, but this does not make the work in addition concrete. The concreteness of these exercises will depend upon the need which children feel of the ability to find the sum of two or more numbers. The beans will be significant, beyond their use as objects, to illustrate the one-to-one correspondence between symbolic representation and reality, only if the problem of summation which at that time engages their attention concerns the sum of certain numbers of beans. Indeed, it may be claimed that the use of one set of objects continuously to illustrate a process in arithmetic hinders rather than helps the child in his ability to reason in this situation, since he may come to consider this chance relationship of beans and addition as essential. He may think that he ought always to add when he is given beans.

A good illustration of the necessity for a well defined problem for guidance when observations are to be made is found in the futility of much work that is done, or rather left undone, when children are taken on excursions. The directions which follow for the conduct of excursions are those which should be followed whenever work in observation is required, those which have reference to the handling of a large group of children in the field being added.

1. The teacher must have clearly defined in her own mind the purpose of the observation. If the teacher has not definitely formulated the problem, the observation of the children will surely be purposeless.

2. It is not enough that the teacher know just what data she expects the children to gather toward the solution of a particular problem; she must know exactly what data are available under the conditions governing the observation.

3. The preliminary work must have prepared children for their observations by giving them very definite problems to solve. Often it will be advantageous to have these problems written in notebooks.

4. Children not only need to want to see, but also need to be directed while they are observing. Nothing is easier than to look and not see that which is essential.

5. It is always advisable to test the success of the observations while they are being made. There is nothing more difficult than to correct a misconception growing out of careless or inadequate observations.

6. It is well to remember that not merely number of observations counts in the solution of a problem. It is rather observations under varying conditions which give weight to our conclusions. One intensive observation may be worth a thousand careless ones.

7. When children are taken on excursions, great care must be exercised to keep them under proper guidance and control. The organization of children into smaller groups with leaders who are made responsible for their proper observance of directions will help. These leaders should have been over the ground with the teacher before the excursion. The assistance of parents, teachers, or of older pupils will at times be necessary.

8. There should be definite work periods during the excursion, just as in the schoolroom or laboratory.

9. A whistle, as a signal for assembling at one point, will help in out-of-door work, provided it is clearly understood that this signal must be obeyed immediately, and under all circumstances.

Comparison and abstraction: With the problem clearly defined and the data provided, the next step consists of comparison and the resulting abstraction of the element present in all of the cases which makes for the solution of the problem. In the ordinary course of our thinking the sequence is as follows: We find ourselves in a situation which presents a problem which demands an adjustment; we make a guess or formulate an hypothesis which furnishes the basis for our work in attempting to solve the problem; we gather data in the light of the hypothesis assumed, which, through comparison and abstraction, leads us to believe our hypothesis correct or false; if the hypothesis seems justified by the data gathered, it is further tested or verified by an appeal to experience; i.e. we endeavor to see whether our conclusion holds in all cases; if this test proves satisfactory, we generalize or define; and lastly this generalization or definition is

used as a point of reference or truth to guide in later thinking or activity.

There is danger that we may overlook the very great importance of inference in this process. We cannot say just when this step in the process will be possible, but it is possibly the most significant of all. A situation presents a problem. Our success in solving the problem depends upon our ability to infer from the facts at our command. Often many inferences will be necessary before we succeed in finding the one that will stand the test. Again with the problem in mind we may be conscious of a great lack of data and may postpone our inference while we collect the needed information. There is one fallacy that must be carefully guarded against in dealing with children, as also with adults; namely, the tendency once the inference has been made to admit only such data as are found to support this particular hypothesis.

It is this ability to infer, to formulate a workable hypothesis, which distinguishes the genius from the man of mediocre ability. It is the ability to see facts in new relations, the giving of new meaning to facts which may be the common possession of all, that characterizes the great thinker. Other people knew many of the facts; but it took the mind of a Newton to discover the relationship existing among these data which he formulated in the law that all bodies attract each other directly in proportion to their weight and inversely in proportion to the square of the distance separating them. As we teach children we should encourage the intelligent guess. We would not, of course, encourage mere random guessing, which may be engaged in by children to have something to say or to blind the teacher. A child who offers a guess or hypothesis should be asked to give his ground for the inference, should show that his guess has grown out of his consideration of the data in hand. It is fallacious to suppose that this kind of thinking is beyond the power of children. They have been forming their inferences and testing them in action from the time that they began to act independently.

There is one element in the consideration of the step of comparison which cannot be too much emphasized, and that is that it is not the comparison of things or situations which present striking

likenesses which gives rise to the highest type of thinking. To look at a dozen horses and then to conclude that all horses have four legs is merely a matter of classification; to observe that the sun, chemical action, electricity, and friction produce heat, and to arrive at the generalization from these cases, apparently so unlike, that heat is a mode of motion is the work of a genius. In general, it is safe to say that we would greatly strengthen our teaching if we were only more careful to see to it that our basis for generalization is found in situations presenting as many variations as possible. For example, if we want to teach a principle in arithmetic, the way to fix it and to make it available for further use by our pupils is not to get a number of problems all of which are alike in form and statement; but rather we should seek as great a variety as is possible in the language used or symbols employed that is compatible with the application of the principle to be taught. In an interesting article on reasoning in primary arithmetic, Professor Suzzallo has pointed out the fact that children’s difficulty in reasoning is often one of language.[8] The trouble has been that teachers have always used a set form, or a very few forms of expression, when they described situations which involved any one of the arithmetical processes. Later when the child is called upon to solve a problem involving this process he does not know which process to apply because he is unfamiliar with the form of expression used. To succeed in teaching children when to add involves the presentation of the situations which call for addition with as great a variation as is possible, i.e. by using not one form, but all of the words or phrases which may be used to indicate summation. In like manner in other fields the examples for comparison will be valuable in proportion as they present variety rather than uniformity in those elements which are not essential. Equally good illustration can be had from any other field. If we want pupils to get any adequate conception of the function of adjectives, we should use examples which involve a variety of adjectives in different parts of sentences. In geography the concept “river” will be clear only when the different types of rivers have been considered and the nonessential elements disregarded.

Generalization: When we feel that we have solved the problem, we are ready to state our generalization. There is considerable advantage in making such a statement. One can never be quite sure that he has solved his problem until he finds himself able to state clearly the results of his thinking. To attempt to define or to generalize is often to realize the inadequacy of our thought on the problem. Children should be encouraged to give their own definition or generalization before referring to that which is provided by the teacher or the book. Indeed, the significance of a generalization for further thinking or later action depends not simply upon one’s ability to repeat words, but rather upon adequate realization of the significance of the conclusion reached. The best test of such comprehension is found in the ability of the pupil to state the generalization for himself.

There is very great danger, if definitions or generalizations are given ready-made to children, that they will learn to juggle with words. The parrot-like repetition of rules of syntax, or principles of arithmetic, never indicates real grasp of these subjects. Children think most when the requirement for thinking is greatest, and none are readier than they to take advantage of laxness on the part of the teacher in this respect. It is not only when the formal statement of principles or definitions is called for that the teacher needs to be on her guard. At any stage of the process, if the teacher will only take their words and read meaning into them, some children will be found ready to substitute words for thought. It is really a mistake to tell a child that you know what he means even though he did not say it. Language is the instrument which he employs in thinking, and, if his statement lacked clearness or definiteness, the chances are very great that his thinking has failed in these same particulars. Instead of encouraging children in loose thinking by accepting any statement offered, it would be much better to raise the question of the real significance of the statement, to inquire just what was meant by the words used. Such procedure will help to make children more careful in expressing themselves, and will inevitably tend to clearer thinking.

Application: Whatever conclusions we have reached, whatever truths we have satisfactorily established, influence us in our later

thought and action. But even though this is true, there is a decided advantage in providing for a definite application of the results of the thinking which children have done as soon as possible and in as many different ways as is feasible. In the first place, such application makes clearer the truth itself, and helps to fix it in mind. Again, the conclusion arrived at to-day is chiefly significant as a basis for our thinking of to-morrow, and it is as we apply our conclusions that new problems arise to stimulate us to further thought. Then, too, the satisfaction which comes when one feels his power over situations as a result of thinking is the very best possible stimulus to further intellectual activity. Finally, we need to show children the application of that which they have learned to the life which they live outside of the school. We are not apt to err on the side of too frequent or too varied application of the generalizations we have led children to make. Rather we shall have to study diligently to provide enough applications to fix for the child the habit of verification by an appeal to experience.

A few words by way of caution concerning the inductive lesson may not be out of place.

First: Not all school work can be undertaken on this general plan. There are times when the end to be accomplished is distinctly not the discovery of some new truth, but rather the fixing of some habit. There are exercises which are distinctively deductive, some which aim to produce habits, and others which seek to secure appreciation. But more of this is in the succeeding chapters.

Second: Even when we seek to establish truth, we cannot always develop it by an appeal to the experience of children nor to observations which they can make. We shall have, on some occasions, to supply the data, and in still other cases it will be most economical to demonstrate the truth of the position which we desire to have them take. There are occasions when the solution of the problem is not possible for children. In this last instance we shall have to provide the authoritative statement. Indeed, it may be argued that one of the lessons which we all need to learn is respect for the expert. We cannot settle all of the problems which arise, but we may choose from among those who profess to have found a solution. Our

education ought to help us to avoid the quack and the charlatan. The habit of logical thinking on the part of children, and expert knowledge in some field, however small, is the only protection which the school can give against the pretensions of those who represent themselves as the dispensers of truth.[9]

Third: There is a grave danger that we may help children too much. Some teachers interpret the inductive development lesson to mean that each step in the thinking required must be carefully prepared for and quickly passed. They consider that they have taught the best lesson when there has been no hitch in the progress from the statement of aim to the wording of the generalization. The suggestive question which makes thinking on the part of children unnecessary is a favorite measure employed. If we stop to consider what thinking means, we cannot fail to see the fallacy of such work. We all do our best thinking, not when the problem to be solved is explained by some one else and all of the difficulties removed, but rather when we find the problem most difficult of solution.

If children are at work on problems which are vital to them, we may expect them to continue to work even though they make mistakes. Indeed, the best recitation may be the one that leaves the children not with a solution skillfully supplied for them by the teacher, but rather with a keen realization of the problem, and with a somewhat clearer idea of the direction in which the solution may be sought. It is the teacher’s work to help the child to see the problem, and, seeing the problem herself from the child’s point of view, to stimulate the child to his best effort. The teacher must know not only the pupil’s attitude of mind toward the problem and how his mind is most likely to react, but also the mental activity required to master properly the issue that has been raised. On the one hand, the teacher’s equipment consists of a knowledge of the minds of the children whom she teaches, and on the other a knowledge of the subject to be taught, not simply as a body of knowledge more or less classified or organized, but as a mode of mental growth.[10] What the teacher needs is a clear realization of the difficulties which the pupils must meet, and the way in which childish minds may best overcome these obstacles. When such sympathy exists between teacher and

pupil, we may expect that pupils will constantly grow stronger in their ability to think logically, instead of becoming more and more dependent upon the teacher. And this is our great work as teachers, to render our services unnecessary.

Fourth: No teacher should attempt to outline her work on the basis of the steps indicated in the discussion of the inductive method without a clear realization of the fact that these steps cannot be sharply differentiated, that they are not mutually exclusive. To define a problem adequately may mean that we have passed through the whole process. At any step in the process after the problem is defined, and some hypothesis formed, we may wish to verify our guess by an appeal to known facts, and often we shall find it necessary to abandon the hypothesis already formed and provide another as a basis for further thinking. It is true that the natural movement of the mind is roughly indicated by the steps named; but it must be remembered that no mind can possibly arrive at the solution of a real problem by adhering to a fixed order of procedure. We do not by our teaching create the power of logical thought; we rather guide a mind that naturally operates logically. We can never teach children to reason, but we can provide the occasion for logical thinking, and can guard against the common fallacies. Our success will depend upon a clear realization of the possibilities of the child mind and of the subjects we teach as part of their growth and development.

Teaching by Types: Teaching by means of types is sometimes discussed as a separate method, while in reality it is simply one form of the inductive process. As was indicated in our discussion of observation above, there are times when the consideration of a single situation or object in detail may be worth more than a thousand careless observations. It is especially true that a thoroughly adequate knowledge of one object or case of a class prepares in the best possible way for future observations of members of the same class. Familiarity with the life history of one animal or plant will help us greatly to understand other animals and plants, because that which is most essential in all has been carefully observed in the case considered. Now let us suppose that several

plants and animals have been studied. If the cases which are considered are truly typical, it may be possible for the student to appreciate not simply the individuals belonging to the classes studied, but also something of the interrelation of the several classes. This illustration, given because it represents in a general way something of the method followed in the study of science, represents a very common method of procedure in the ordinary affairs of life. None of us can hope to support our conclusions by a careful scrutiny of all possible cases. We take something on authority; namely, that the individual case considered is representative of a large group, then after we have investigated the one case we apply our conclusions to the whole group. Of course there is one great danger. We may be overhasty in our generalizations. No fallacy is more common than the emphasis placed upon non-essentials by those whose observations have been limited. The stories of the traveler who generalizes, after seeing one red-headed child or after eating at one hotel, concerning the children and hotels of the country visited, are too common to need repetition here. Where observations are necessarily limited, the important consideration is to get cases that seem as different as possible in order that that which is essential may be differentiated from the nonessential or accidental.

Teaching by types in our ordinary school work has been applied most frequently to the subject of geography. Applying the principle stated above, we shall be careful in teaching rivers, mountains, cities, commerce, or any other geographical notion to see to it that the individual cases considered are as widely different as possible. To teach New York City, Philadelphia, and Chicago only would give children a very erroneous idea of the concept “city.” They are all exceptionally large, all American, all modern. There are cities smaller, with peculiarities due to age, to location, and to the ideas and resources of the people building them. A better selection would be New York City, London, Tokyo, Venice, Cairo, and Munich. Objection could still very well be offered that this list is too short to include all classes. There can be no doubt that to have taught any city carefully will aid greatly in understanding the notion “city” and in appreciating other cities, but manifestly any final generalization

concerning cities must wait until our knowledge of geography has been widely extended. The same conclusion would be reached were any other notion of geography, or any other study, subjected to the same test. There is, however, no harm in forming tentative judgments. Indeed, we must all do this every day of our lives. The main issue is to see to it that there is no mistake as to the tentative character of the conclusions reached, that the open-minded attitude be preserved.

F C R

C. A. and F. M. McMurry, The Method of the Recitation, Chapters VI to IX inclusive.

John Dewey, How We Think, Chapters XII to XV inclusive. Exercises.

1. What is the purpose of the step of preparation in the inductive lesson? When would you begin an inductive lesson with a statement of aim or problem? What value is there in having children state the aim of a lesson? When during the lesson should the aim be referred to?

2. How would you hope to have country children get a clear idea of a city? Could you develop this idea with sufficient definiteness by asking questions?

3 What preparation would you think necessary for a class that were taking their first trip to a dairy?

4. What was wrong in the class where, after a trip to the country, a small child said, “A cow is a small animal with four legs that likes to live in the mud and grunt”?

5 Would you allow a boy to perform an experiment in nature study that you knew would result unsatisfactorily?

6. A teacher used the following sentences in her attempt to teach the function of an adjective; criticize the list given

The red apple is sweet.

The green grass is soft.

The yellow house is large.

The tall man is sick.

The largest horse is fast.

Suggest a better list of sentences for the purpose indicated

7. In what sense is it true that an induction begins with a generalization? How do you proceed when you modify a generalization which you once held as true?

8. A pupil defined a river as a stream of water flowing through the land. How would you hope to secure a more accurate generalization from him?

9 What is the function of a lecture on Germany to a group of children studying the geography of Europe? Do you think such a lecture would be as valuable as a lesson in which the pupils are asked to find out why German commerce has developed so rapidly during the past twenty years?

10. Under what conditions would you require children to commit to memory the definitions found in their textbooks?

11 If your pupils were reading Kipling’s Jungle Book, would you try to make your lessons inductive?

12. What difficulties would you encounter in trying to teach children who live in the Mississippi Valley the meaning of the term mountain? How could you hope to overcome these difficulties?

13. The following illustrative problems were used by a teacher who was presenting the subject of percentage to a class for the first time. Can you improve the list?

A man who had $10,000 lost 25 per cent of his money How much did he lose?

A horse which cost $250 was sold at a loss of 10 per cent. How much did the owner lose?

A house which cost $25,000 was burned It was insured for 50 per cent of its value How much did the owner receive from the insurance company?

A suit of clothes which cost the dealer $18 was sold at a gain of 25 per cent. How much did the dealer gain on the suit?

14 Which would be better, to tell a group of children of a trip which you took to a cattle ranch, show them pictures, and possibly read a description of ranch life, or spend the same amount of time questioning these same children in the hope of developing some adequate idea of this type of life? If you follow the first method, could you be sure that children had derived accurate ideas from your description?

15 Write a series of questions which you would use in developing the generalization, “Men who live in cities are dependent upon those who live in the country for the necessities of life ”

16. How would you defend the following statement: It is more important that a pupil should have worked out the solution of a single problem in which he is interested, than that he should have learned, without solving the problems for himself, the answers to a dozen problems from books which he is asked to read.

Turn static files into dynamic content formats.

Create a flipbook
Issuu converts static files into: digital portfolios, online yearbooks, online catalogs, digital photo albums and more. Sign up and create your flipbook.