Instant download Food, justice, and animals josh milburn pdf all chapter

Page 1


Food, Justice, and Animals Josh Milburn

Visit to download the full and correct content document: https://ebookmass.com/product/food-justice-and-animals-josh-milburn/

More products digital (pdf, epub, mobi) instant download maybe you interests ...

44.1644° North Josh Lanyon

https://ebookmass.com/product/44-1644-north-josh-lanyon/

Please Report Your Bug Here Josh Riedel

https://ebookmass.com/product/please-report-your-bug-here-joshriedel/

Saving Food : Production, Supply Chain, Food Waste, and

Food Consumption Galanakis

https://ebookmass.com/product/saving-food-production-supplychain-food-waste-and-food-consumption-galanakis/

Making AI Intelligible Herman Cappelen & Josh Dever [Cappelen

https://ebookmass.com/product/making-ai-intelligible-hermancappelen-josh-dever-cappelen/

Animals and Business Ethics Natalie Thomas

https://ebookmass.com/product/animals-and-business-ethicsnatalie-thomas/

Making Sense of ‘Food’ Animals: A Critical Exploration of the Persistence of ‘Meat’ 1st ed. 2020 Edition Paula Arcari

https://ebookmass.com/product/making-sense-of-food-animals-acritical-exploration-of-the-persistence-of-meat-1sted-2020-edition-paula-arcari/

Saving Animals, Saving Ourselves: Why Animals Matter for Pandemics, Climate Change, and Other Catastrophes

Jeff Sebo

https://ebookmass.com/product/saving-animals-saving-ourselveswhy-animals-matter-for-pandemics-climate-change-and-othercatastrophes-jeff-sebo/

The Political Soul : Plato on Thumos, Spirited Motivation, and the City Josh Wilburn

https://ebookmass.com/product/the-political-soul-plato-on-thumosspirited-motivation-and-the-city-josh-wilburn/

Introduction to Food Science and Food Systems 2nd Edition Rick Parker

https://ebookmass.com/product/introduction-to-food-science-andfood-systems-2nd-edition-rick-parker/

Food,Justice,andAnimals

Food,Justice,and

JoshMilburn

GreatClarendonStreet,Oxford,OX26DP, UnitedKingdom

OxfordUniversityPressisadepartmentoftheUniversityofOxford. ItfurtherstheUniversity’sobjectiveofexcellenceinresearch,scholarship, andeducationbypublishingworldwide.Oxfordisaregisteredtrademarkof OxfordUniversityPressintheUKandincertainothercountries ©JoshMilburn2023

Themoralrightsoftheauthorhavebeenasserted Allrightsreserved.Nopartofthispublicationmaybereproduced,storedin aretrievalsystem,ortransmitted,inanyformorbyanymeans,withoutthe priorpermissioninwritingofOxfordUniversityPress,orasexpresslypermitted bylaw,bylicenceorundertermsagreedwiththeappropriatereprographics rightsorganization.Enquiriesconcerningreproductionoutsidethescopeofthe aboveshouldbesenttotheRightsDepartment,OxfordUniversityPress,atthe addressabove

Youmustnotcirculatethisworkinanyotherform andyoumustimposethissameconditiononanyacquirer

PublishedintheUnitedStatesofAmericabyOxfordUniversityPress 198MadisonAvenue,NewYork,NY10016,UnitedStatesofAmerica

BritishLibraryCataloguinginPublicationData

Dataavailable

LibraryofCongressControlNumber:2023900813

ISBN978–0–19–286746–9

DOI:10.1093/oso/9780192867469.001.0001

Printedandboundby CPIGroup(UK)Ltd,Croydon,CR04YY

LinkstothirdpartywebsitesareprovidedbyOxfordingoodfaithand forinformationonly.Oxforddisclaimsanyresponsibilityforthematerials containedinanythirdpartywebsitereferencedinthiswork.

Acknowledgements

Iwrotethisbookfrom2019to2022,whileIwasaBritishAcademyPostdoctoralFellow.IthanktheBritishAcademyandmyhostinstitutions:the UniversityofSheffieldandLoughboroughUniversity.

ParticularthanksareowedtoAlasdairCochrane,whosesupportthroughouttheplanningandwritingofthisbookwasinvaluable.Idevisedand refinedtheprojectinconversationwithAlasdair,andheofferedcomments ondraftsofeverychapter.

ReviewersatOxfordUniversityPressalsoofferedextensive,valuablecommentsonthisproject.OneofthesereviewerswasJeffSebo,whokindly continuedtooffercommentsafterthecompletionofthereviewprocess,and helpedshapethebook.

Ipresentedanddiscussedideasfromthebookinmultipleoutlets,includingarangeofpresentationsattheUniversityofSheffield;invitedlecturesat AberystwythUniversityandtheUniversityofWinchester;multiplepresentationsattheMANCEPTWorkshopsinManchester;andpresentationsat theconferencesoftheAustralasianAnimalStudiesAssociation,theEuropeanAssociationforCriticalAnimalStudies,andTheVeganSociety.Ithank audiencesfor—oftencritical!—commentsanddiscussionontheseoccasions.

Ideasinthebook,however,stretchbackadecadetowhenIfirstseriously startedthinkingaboutfoodandfoodsystemsinmypostgraduatestudies.It isthusimpossibletonameeverybodytowhomIowethanksinadditionto thoseabove,butamongthemareDavidArchardandJeremyWatkins,my doctoralsupervisorsatQueen’sUniversityBelfast;SueDonaldsonandWill Kymlicka,withwhomIworkedonapreviouspostdoctoralprojectatthe unrelatedQueen’sUniversityinKingston,Ontario;BobFischer,withwhom Ihaveco-writtenmultiplepapersontheethicsofeatinganimalproducts; andMatteoBonotti,whofirstencouragedmetothinkaboutfoodpolicyand offeredhelpfuladviceonthisproject.

ImustalsoacknowledgetheongoingsupportofmyfiancéeBecca,who championsmyworkifnotalwaysmyconclusions,andofmydogsHollieand Casper,whomadetheyearsoftheCOVID-19pandemic,whileIwrotethis book,abitbrighter.

Acknowledgements

IdedicatethisbooktoSiobhanO’Sullivan,whowasdiagnosedwithovariancancerin2020.Siobhanisachampionofanimals,andabelieverinthe powerofacademicworktomaketheworldbetterforthem.Her Animals, Equality,andDemocracy(2011)wasapathbreakingextensionofliberalpoliticalthoughttoanimalprotection,andIamproudtothinkof Food,Justice, andAnimals asfirmlyinthesametradition.

Introduction

Imaginetheburgerbarofabettertomorrow—of2030,or2050,or2100,or 2500.What’sonthemenu?Maybewecanimaginewidespreadchangesto makeamoreaccessiblefoodsystem.Themenucouldfeaturetheburgers,fries, andicecreamoftoday,butwithmuchlowerpricetags.Orwemightimaginewidespreadchangestomakea healthier foodsystem.Maybetheburgers arereplacedwithleanchicken,thefrieswithsalad,theicecreamwithfruit. Orwemightimaginewidespreadchangestomakeamore environmentally sustainable foodsystem.Maybebeefisoffthemenu,butsustainablyfarmed fishremains.

Butwecouldalsoimaginewidespreadchangestomakeamore animalfriendly foodsystem,orevenonethatrespectsanimals’ rights. Whatwould beonthemenuthen?

Tosupportourcurrenteatinghabits,tensofbillionsofvertebratesare slaughteredannually.Manyhavelivedlivesofsufferingathumanhands.Trillionsoffish—wildandfarmed—arekilledannually.AndIcouldinflatethese numbersenormouslybyincluding other animals1 killedfor,orinpursuit of,food—invertebratesofallkinds,malechickskilledintheeggindustry, animalshuntedandtrappedforfood,andsoon.Itisthefoodsystemthat facessomeofthelargestchangesifwe(asasociety)aregoingtotakeanimals seriously.

Supposeanimalshaverights.Thismeansthattherearecertainthingsthat cannotbedonetothemwithoutinjustice.We,collectively,shouldprotect thoserights,ideallythroughthepowerofthestate.Thisisnotabookabout whatrightsanimalshave,orthereasonsthattheyhaverights.Thereare alreadylotsofbooksaboutthosethings.Instead,thisbookstartswithanimals’rights,andaskswhatastatethatrespectsthemlookslike.Itfocuseson thefoodsystemofthisstate,asitis(arguably)thecontemporaryfoodsystem thatisresponsibleforthemostegregiousviolationsofanimals’rights.Ifthe stateisconcernedwithprotectinganimals’rights,thatraisesgraveconcerns aboutourfoodsystem.Indeed,itraisesgraveconcernsaboutfoodsystems

1 Intheinterestsofreadability,Ifollowtheconventionalpracticeofusingtheword animals toreferto animalsotherthanhumans.Thisisimprecise,ashumansarealsoanimals.

Food,Justice,andAnimals.JoshMilburn,OxfordUniversityPress.©JoshMilburn(2023). DOI:10.1093/oso/9780192867469.003.0001

altogether.Isthereaviablealternativefoodsystemthatrespectsanimals’ rights?

Itmightseemthattheresponseisobvious.Ifjusticeentitlesanimalsto legallyprotectedrights,thenourfoodsystemswillhavetobeplant-based. Animalsmaynotbekeptsothattheycanbekilledandtheirbodiesbeturned intomeat,orsothattheycanbekeptalive(foratime)fortheirbodiesto producemilk,eggs,honey,orotherproductsthatendupinfood.

ButIamnotsurethisanswerisright.Infact,itistheclaimofthisbookthat ourfoodsystemsdonotneedtobefullyplant-based,eventhoughanimalsare entitledtolegallyprotectedrights.Wecertainlycannotkillortortureanimals forfood,buttheycanstillbeinvolvedinourfoodsystems,andwecanstill eatanimalproducts.

Consequently,Iproposethattheanimal-rights-respectingstatecould containaveritablecornucopiaofanimalproducts:themeatofallkinds ofvertebrateandinvertebrateanimals;birds’eggs;mammals’milk;anda rangeoffoodstuffsproducedusinginvertebrates,suchashoney,shellac,and cochineal.Whatismore,theruralspacesofthishypotheticalstatecouldstill havefieldsofcows,sheep,chickens,goats,andotherdomesticatedanimals. Notonlycouldtherebeanimalproteinforthehungryandthosewhovalue it,buttherecouldbeworkwithanimalsforthosewhowantit.Notthebrutal workoftheslaughterhouseorfactoryfarm,but good work—humane work. Perhapsinthisstate,wewillhaveourcow,but,ifwewantto,wewilleat her,too.

Myvisionofananimal-rights-respectingstateisavisionofastatein whichwedonotkillanimalsormakethemsufferforhumanpurposes, fromthetrivialtothequiteconsequential.Borrowinganevocativeterm fromSueDonaldsonandWillKymlicka(2011)—withoutcommittingtothe detailsoftheirposition—Icallthisthe zoopolis.Thezoopolisisastatein whichanimalsarerespectedasindividuals,entitledtoliveasapartofour community—and,indeed,entitledtoaffectthedirectionofourcommunity, throughinvolvementwithpoliticalprocesses.Nonetheless,andtorepeat,I believethezoopolisisastateinwhichanimalproductscould—should—be available.How?Gettingtothebottomofthisquestionisthepointofthis book.

Inthechaptersthatfollow,Iexplorearangeofpossibleroutestoanimalproteinthatare,mightbe,orcouldbeconsistentwithfullrespectfor animals’rights,andarethusthekindsofelementsthatmaybepartofan all-things-consideredbestfoodsystemforthezoopolis.Inbrief,Iarguethat someanimalsarenon-sentient(orarealmostcertainlynotsentient)andthus weowethemnothingdirectly—wemayutilizethemfreely.Oystersmightbe

anexample.Others probably arenotsentient,sowecanutilizethemwith caution.Insectsmaybelonginthiscategory.

Otheranimalsaresentient,orprobablyso,andsoweowethemconsiderablerespect—namely,rights.However,wecould,consistentwiththisrespect, welcomethemintoourcommunitiesandworkplaces,andwork with them toproducethingsofbenefittoall.Theconfinement,objectification,mutilation,andslaughterofcontemporaryanimalagriculture—even‘high-welfare’, ‘local’,‘organic’animalagriculture—isinimicaltorespectinganimals’rights. Butworkingwithanimalstoproduceeggs,milk,wool,andmoreneednotbe. (Particularlyimportant,forreasonsIwillmakeclear,isworkingwithanimals for cells.)

Whataboutmeat?‘Plant-basedmeat’promisesburgers,nuggets,and evensteaksculinarilyindistinguishablefrom‘traditional’,orslaughter-based, meat.Meanwhile,‘cellularagriculture’promises‘cultivated’meat—whichis, inprinciple, physically indistinguishablefromslaughter-basedmeat—with onlytheslightestanimalinput.Crucially,wewillsee,thepracticeof meat-eatingisnot itself rights-violating—evenif(almost)allthewaysthat wecurrentlyacquiremeat are rights-violating.Andbothplant-based‘animal’productsandcellularagriculturestretchbeyondmeat.Icontendthat plant-basedorcultivatedmilk,eggs,honey,andmoremaybeavailableinthe zoopolis.

Iexploredetailsoftheseaspectsofhypotheticalfoodsystemsoverthe remainderofthebook,andIofferamoredetailedchapter-by-chapterbreakdownattheendofthisintroduction.Fornow,however,itisimportantto brieflysituatethepresentstudy.

Animals,rights,andpolitics

Wecanroughlysplitanimalrightsscholarshipinhalf.Coretothe‘old’animal rights(Regan1983;Francione2000)isagroundinginmoralphilosophyand, crucially,afocusonveganism.Contrastingitselfto‘welfarism’—mainstream inbothanimalactivism(see Francione1996)andethicalstudyofhuman–animalrelationships(see Singer1975)—oldanimalrightsdidnotsupport simplymakinganimalagriculturemorehumane.Itsupported abolishing animalagriculture,andhumanuseofanimals,alltogether.AsTomRegan putit,

Whenitcomestohowhumansexploitanimals,recognitionoftheirrightsrequires abolition,notreform.Beingkindtoanimalsisnotenough.Avoidingcrueltyisnot

enough.Whetherweexploitanimalstoeat,towear,toentertainus,ortolearn,the truthofanimalrightsrequiresemptycages,notlargercages.

(Regan2004a,10)

Inoldanimalrights,veganismisa‘moralbaseline’—thebareminimumwe oweanimals(Francione2012).

Whatisveganism?Forthepurposesofthisbook,Iaminterestedin veganismasitrelatestofood.Itreat‘vegan’and‘plant-based’asroughsynonyms,adoptingapractice-baseddefinition,accordingtowhichveganismis aboutabstentionfromanimalproducts,ratherthanpoliticalcommitments (DicksteinandDutkiewicz2021).Avegandietorfoodsystemisonewithout animalproducts.Avegandietorfoodsystemmaybeconsistentwithanimal rights.Itmaybethe only foodsystemordietconsistentwithanimalrights. ButIcontendthatthesearequestionsworthexploring;theyarenottrue by definition.

Advocatesofoldanimalrightsmadeacaseforveganismin moral,rather than political,terms.Wecancertainlyexaggeratetheextenttowhichthe advocatesofthisoldapproachwereapolitical(Cochrane,Garner,and O’Sullivan2018),buttheyweregenerallyexpressingthemselvesas—andread by—moralphilosophers.Ifadvocatesofthisoldapproachdidofferapolitical philosophy(see,e.g.,Schmitz2016),theywoulddefendplant-basedstates,far removedfromthoseenvisionedinthisbook.

Butthereisalsoa‘new’animalrights,groundedin political philosophy,ratherthanmoralphilosophy.Therehasbeen,inthewordsofmany commentators,a‘politicalturn’inanimalethics(AhlhausandNiesen 2015; Milligan2015; DonaldsonandKymlicka2017; Cochrane,Garner, andO’Sullivan2018).Thisopensanimalethics—thenormativestudyof human–animalrelationships,thestudyofhowwe ought tointeractwith animals—tonewvocabulariesandconcepts.Butitalsoopensnewquestions.Forexample,animalethicistshavemovedfromaskingindividualistic questionsaboutanimals(‘ShouldIbevegan?’‘Howdoesavirtuousperson treattheirdog?’‘Whatisthevalueofananimalrelativetoahuman?’)toask moresocietal,socio-politicalquestions(‘Whatlawsshouldprotectanimals?’ ‘Whatformsofdemocracyaregoodforanimals?’‘Cananimalsbeourcocitizens?’).

Theoristsofthis‘new’approachtoanimalrightsdointerrogatefood(e.g. DonaldsonandKymlicka2011,134–139; Cochrane2012,chapter 4; Wayne 2013),settingupinoppositiontothe‘abolitionism’ofoldanimalrights.Veganismceasestobeamoralbaseline,andrespectforanimalrightsceases

tomeantheendofhuman–animalinteractions.Consequently,theoristsof newanimalrightsareexplicitlyopentonon-vegandietsandstates,buttheir commentsstopshortofworked-outfoodsystems.Perhapstheenvisioned productiononlyworksonasmallscale—individualsorsmallcommunities— andthusfallshortofbeingacontenderforafood system.Alternatively,or additionally,commentsonfoodproductionmaybebrief,inconclusive,or scattered.

Take,forinstance,DonaldsonandKymlicka.Wecanputasidethedetails oftheirframeworkfornow—letussimplyaskwhattheysayaboutthefood systemofthezoopolis.Theansweris:surprisinglylittle.Likealladvocatesof animalrights,oldornew,theyseecontemporaryfoodsystemsasbeyondthe pale.Recognizinganimals’rights,theysay,meansrecognizingthatanimals werenotputontheearthtofeedus,whiletherightsthemselvesrule‘out virtuallyallexistingpracticesoftheanimal-useindustries’(Donaldsonand Kymlicka2011,40).Theyconsequentlyspeakinglowingtermsofa‘switch toveganism…onasocietalscale’(2011,202).

ThisrejectionofanimalfoodsleadsRobertGarner,anotheradvocateof newanimalrights,tolamentamissedopportunityfornoveltyinDonaldsonandKymlicka’swork.Forhim,their‘startingpointistheacceptance, asabaseline,ofatraditionalspecies-egalitarianabolitionistanimalrights agenda’(Garner2013,103)—theoldapproachtoanimalrightsagainstwhich DonaldsonandKymlickapositionthemselves.GarnerseesDonaldsonand Kymlickaasofferingapoliticizedvisionoftheoldanimalrights.Their framework,hesays,

hastheeffectofrulingoutofaccountthedomesticationofanimalsforexploitativehumanpurposes.Animalagriculture[is]thereforemorallyillegitimateonthe groundsthattouseanimalsinsuchawayistoinfringetheirrights.…[Donaldson andKymlicka]adoptananimalrightsethicthatrulesouttheuseofanimalsfor food[.]

(Garner2013,104)

ButGarnerisonlyhalfright.ForDonaldsonandKymlicka,co-livingwith animals can beconsistentwithsharingmilkwithcows,oreatingeggslaidby chickens,orgatheringwool(forfoodadditives)fromsheep(2011,136–139). Andtheyaskquestionsaboutboththecorpsesofanimalswhohave diednaturallyoraccidentally,andaboutcellularagriculture—twopotentiallyrights-respectingsourcesofmeat(2011,151–152).Theydonotraise someotherquestions.Forexample,theydonotaddress(sodonotruleout)

humanseatingnon-sentientanimals,2 andtheydonotaddresscellularagriculturebeyondcultivatedmeat.

Thereare,however,atleastthreereasonstoquestionDonaldsonandKymlicka’sscatteredcommentsonusinganimalsforfood.And,torepeat,my explorationofDonaldsonandKymlicka’scommentsisindicative.Icould levelsimilarcriticismatotherscholarsofnewanimalrights.

First,DonaldsonandKymlickahedgetheirarguments,reachingnofirm conclusionsaboutanimalproducts.Whiletheydonotruleanimalproducts out,neitherdotheyreallyendorsethem.

Second,DonaldsonandKymlickadonotexplorethereasonsthatwemight haveforendorsingnon-veganfoodsystems,evenasadvocatesofanimal rights.Tobeclear,therearesuchreasons. Garner(2013) offersarguments aboutthe practical benefitsforanimalsandtheanimal-rightsmovement; hisreasonsarepragmatic.Myownreasons,exploredinChapter 1,are principled.

Third,andperhapsmostsurprisingly,DonaldsonandKymlicka’sdiscussionsofanimalproductsarenoticeablysmall-scale.Theirdiscussionsevoke imagesof,forexample,familieskeepingchickensinbackyardsandcollecting(thoughnotselling)eggs,orindividualscollectingthecorpsesofanimals killedontheroadtofeedcompanioncats.Thereseemstobelittlebywayof afood system emergingfromtheseideas.

Thus,onhowcitizensofthezoopoliseat,DonaldsonandKymlickaare caughtbetweenthestraightforward—abolitionist—visionoftheveganstate, and somethingelse.Thissomethingelseisafoodsystemfarfromthosein twenty-firstcenturystates(oranyhistoricalstate),butitisunspecified,or,at least,underspecified.Itisthegoalofthisbooktospecifythat‘somethingelse’, andofferavisionofanon-veganfoodsystemthatmightsustainthezoopolis.PerhapsthatzoopolisresemblesDonaldsonandKymlicka’svision,but perhapsitresemblesoneofthe(moreorless)competingorcomplementary visionsofferedbyother(moreorless)liberalthinkersworkinginthe‘political turn’.Irefertomanyofthesethinkers’ideasoverthecomingchapters.

Thisbookoffersclearstepstowardsafoodsystemforanimalrights theory—butafoodsystemfor new animalrights,andalong-neededalternativetothefoodsystemoftheabolitionists.But,morethanthis,itoffersafood systemthatpeoplecommittedtoawiderangeofcompetingvalues—animal advocatesandanimalagriculturalists;vegansandfoodies;environmentalists andfood-justiceadvocates—couldchampion.

2 DonaldsonandKymlickaaresentientists(seeChapter 2),sotheywillnotconceivenon-sentient animalsasrightsbearers.Tomyknowledge,however,theyneveraddressthisissueexplicitly.

Animalsandjustice

Fortheoristsofanimalrights,oldornew,thestandardpracticesofwesternanimalagricultureareunjust.Withfewexceptions,itisunjustto slaughteranimals;confinethemtocrampedsheds;mutilatethem.Thus,for animal-rightstheorists(incontrasttosomeotheranimalethicists)justicehas alwaysbeenimportant.However,forthetheoristsofnewanimalrights,itis central—adefiningconcern.Asthreescholarscentraltothepoliticalturn putit,

thecrucialunifyinganddistinctivefeatureofthesecontributions[toanimalethics inpoliticalphilosophy]—andwhatcanproperlybesaidtomarkthemoutasa ‘politicalturn’—isthewayinwhichtheyimaginehowpoliticalinstitutions,structuresandprocessesmightbe transformed soastosecurejusticeforbothhuman andnon-humananimals.Putsimply,theessentialfeatureofthepoliticalturnis this constructive focusonjustice.

(Cochrane,Garner,andO’Sullivan2018,263–264)

Itshouldbeclearthatthecurrentprojectaimstoimaginehowpolitical institutions,structures,andprocesses—specifically,foodsystems—mightbe transformed.Butwhat,precisely,is justice?

JusticehasbeencentraltopoliticalphilosophysinceatleastPlato’s Republic,whichisessentiallyanenquiryintothemeaningofjustice.For Plato,justiceisultimatelyabouteverything(includingpeople)beinginits (their)properplace,andthusabouteverything(includingsocietyasawhole) beingbalanced.Incontemporarypoliticalphilosophy,afocusonjusticeis owedinparttoJohnRawls.Hedistinguishesbetweenthe concept ofjusticeandvaried conceptions ofjustice.Iwillreturntospecificconceptions shortly,butwhattheyshare—andthuswhatgetstothebottomofthe concept ofjustice—isthattheyoffer:

principlesforassigningbasicrightsanddutiesandfordeterminingwhattheytake tobetheproperdistributionofthebenefitsandburdensofsocialcooperation.

…Thosewhoholddifferentconceptionsofjusticecan,then,stillagreethatinstitutionsarejustwhennoarbitrarydistinctionsaremadebetweenpersonsinthe assigningofbasicrightsanddutiesandwhentherulesdetermineaproperbalancebetweencompetingclaimstotheadvantagesofsociallife.Mencanagree tothisdescriptionofjustinstitutionssincethenotionsofanarbitrarydistinction andofaproperbalance,whichareincludedintheconceptofjustice,areleftopen foreachtointerpretaccordingtotheprinciplesofjusticethatheaccepts.These

principlessingleoutwhichsimilaritiesanddifferencesamongpersonsarerelevant indeterminingrightsanddutiesandtheyspecifywhichdivisionofadvantagesis appropriate.

(Rawls1999,5)

WhenRawlssays persons,heisimagininghumans—orperhaps some humans.But(becauseanimalscanbepersons,becausejusticecanstretch beyondpersons,orboth)weneednotlimitjusticetohumans.Thepointof thepoliticalturninanimalethicsisthatdiscussionsofjusticeinthetwentiethcenturyignoredanimals—theoristsrelegatedquestionsaboutanimals to‘mere’morality.Atbest,questionsaboutanimalswerea later or derivative questionforjustice,ratherthansomethingtheoristsmustprincipallyaddress (see Nussbaum2007,chapter 1).

Justiceforanimalsshouldnotariseonly‘after’wehaveresolvedquestions aboutjusticeforhumans—intheory or practice.Justiceisimportantforanimalsbecausethedemandsofjusticeareparticularlystringent.Theyarenot merelythingsitwouldbe nice or good or charitable or virtuous todo.They arenoteventhingsthatweshouldinsistupon—atleast,weshouldnotstop at insistence.Instead,thedemandsofjusticearesostringentthatpeoplemight legitimately coerce othersintomeetingthem.

Forexample,itmightbenice,good,charitable,orvirtuousofmetodonate muchofmyincometoaworthycharity.Ifmymoralconvictionsleadmeto endorsetheeffectivealtruismmovement,orIslam’s zakah principle,3 Imight eventhinkIam morallyrequired todonate.ButitisunlikelythatIthinkthat Iam requiredbyjustice todonatelargeamounts.Indeed,thissoundsparadoxical;ifIamrequiredbyjusticetodonate,itdoesnotsoundlike donation atall.Donationsare,bydefinition,supererogatory(thatis,theygobeyond myduty).IfIfailto‘donate’whenrequiredbyjusticetodoso,thenothers (likelyactingonbehalfofthestate)may(orshould) force metodonate,and perhapspunishme.

Infocusingonjustice,politicalphilosophyisahigh-stakesbranchofethics: ‘It’snotjustaboutwhatpeopleoughttodo,it’saboutwhatpeoplearemorally permitted,andsometimesmorallyrequired, tomakeeachotherdo’(Swift 2013,24,emphasisadded).

Ifourdutiestowardsanimalsaremattersofmeremorality,then,nomatterhowimportanttheyarewithinourmoraltheory,wehavenobusiness forcingeachothertoobeythem.Inaliberalsociety,disagreementsabout

3 IthankananonymousUniversityofSheffieldstudentforthisexample.

moralityaretobetolerated.IfIthinkalcoholisimmoral,butyouthinkteetotalismisprudishself-abnegation,thensobeit.Wemustacceptthatthe otheris(perceivedtobe)wrong.Youhavenobusinessforcingmetotryfine wines,andIhavenobusinessstoppingyoufromenjoyingthem.Toborrow thewordsofJohnStuartMill,althoughnotingtheywereoriginallypresented inaslightlydifferentcontext,myfeelingthatsomeoneisnotbehavingin accordancewiththe(frommypointofview,andforallanyoneelseknows, true)normsofvirtuousconsumptionmightpresent‘goodreasonsforremonstratingwithhim,orreasoningwithhim,orpersuadinghim,orentreating him,butnotforcompellinghim,orvisitinghimwithanyevilincasehedo otherwise’(Mill2008,14).

Itshouldthusbeclearwhyrelegatingharmstoanimalstothedomainof themerelymoralwillbeverybadforanimalsinaliberalstate(Garner2013, chapter 3).Imagineyouthinkitmorallyacceptable—evenmorallygood—to doawfulthingstoanimals.Imagine,forexample,thatyouareagourmetof themostmorallydubiouskind,andthinkthatitis good thatpeoplecatch ortolanbuntings,stabouttheireyes,forcefeedthem,thendrownthemin brandysothattheycanberoastedandeaten.Orconsiderotherostensibly cruelfoodstuffs,whichyoumightthinkit good toexperience:thefoiegras ofFrance,whichinvolvesfarmersforce-feedingbirdstoengorgetheirlivers;the ikizukuri ofJapan,whichinvolveschefscuttingandservinglivefish, octopuses,andothers;lobsters,whocooksdropliveintoboilingwater;orthe YinYangfish(‘dead-and-alivefish’)ofTaiwan,whichhasadeep-friedbody, attachedtoastill-livinghead.

Ormaybeyouthinkitisgoodthatchefssupportkillinganimalsparticularly rare,orparticularlyintelligent,orparticularlyhuman-like,toofferunrivalled diningexperiences:CentralAfricanbushmeatmadefromgorillasandchimpanzees;JapaneseorFaroesecuisinecontainingdolphinorwhalemeat;dogs bredfortheKoreandog-meattrade.

Imagine,too,thatyouareunmoved—toevokeMill—bymyremonstrating,reasoning,persuading,orentreating.Whatthen?Intheliberalstate,if ourdutiestoanimalsarenotmattersofjustice,Imustsimplytolerateyour egregiouslyharmfulbehaviour,justastheteetotallerandsommeliermust tolerateeachother.

Butsomeoneseemstohavebeenforgotten,here.Peoplewithdifferent visionsofthegoodlifetoleratingeachother’spursuitofhappinessisone thing.Indeed,itiscentraltothecurrentproject.Butwhenthatpursuitofhappinessinvolvessomeoneelse—theFrenchgoose,theKoreandog,theFaroese whale—questionsofjusticeenter.

Thisiswhereitisworthreintroducing conceptions ofjustice.Thisbook beginswiththecontentionthatanimalshaverights.Asaconceptionofjustice(or,moreprecisely,setofconceptions,orpartofaconception),animal rightstakesasarbitrarytheideathathumansaresomeones,aboutwhomjusticeclaimscanbemade,whileanimalsaresomethings,theuseofwhichmust betolerated.(Astoryaboutwhatconstitutesanarbitrarydistinctioninthe attributionofrightsandduties,recall,iskeytoRawls’sexplanationofconceptionsofjustice.)Andifanimalsaresomeones,entitledtoprotection,it isonlynaturalthatthisisputintothelanguageofrights.Likejustice,rights canbeunderstoodasthosemoralentitlementsforwhichonecan‘demandor enforcecompliance’(Nozick1981,499).Forpoliticalphilosophy,then,rights arecentral.Thisisbecausepoliticalphilosophy,initsfocusonjustice,isthe ‘theoryofwhatbehaviorlegitimatelymaybeenforced,andofthenatureof theinstitutionalstructurethatstayswithinandsupportstheseenforceable rights’(Nozick1981,503).

InthisNozickianlanguage,myquestioninthisbookiswhichwaysof acquiringfoodthestatemayprohibit,and,moreimportantly,whichthey may not,toensurethatthestatedoesnotoverstepitsmark.Forliberals,any restrictionoffreedomisregrettable.Wemustensurethatanimalrightsdonot become,inthewordsofonecritic,toolsthat‘onlyconferadditionalpoweron governmentsandbureaucratstorunourlivesforus’,ratherthangenuineprotectionsforanimals(Machan2004,23).Stateinterferencewithlibertymust gofarenoughtorealizejustice—forhumans and animals—butnofurther.If itgoesfurther,thestatewill,itself,beguiltyofunjustimpositions.Achieving justiceisadelicatebusiness.Toolittleinterference,andonesetofindividuals(here,animals)loseprotectionstowhichtheyareentitled.Toomuch, andanothersetofindividuals(here,humans)loselibertiestowhichtheyare entitled.

Butthereisapuzzlehere,whichImustacknowledge.Itisfinetosay wemusttoleratedisagreementsaboutmorality,whilewecanenforcethe demandsofjustice.Butthereisdisagreementaboutwhatconstitutesjustice. Forexample,manyliberalswilldisagreethatanimalshaverights.Well,so beit—again,thisisnotabookarguingthatanimalshaverights,itisabook exploringtheconsequencesofanimalrights.Ifmycriticsprefer:itisabook exploringwhatitwouldmean ifanimalshadrights.

Butthisdoesnotsolvetheproblem,asthereisstillroomfordisagreement betweenadvocatesofanimalrightsabout which rightsanimalshave—or whichofourdutiestoanimalscrossthelinefrom mere moralitytoissues ofjustice.Ihopetosidestepmanyofthesedisagreements,butIwillsaya littlemoreabouttherightsanimalshavelaterinthisintroduction.

AndyetthereismoredisagreementImustacknowledge.Thereis disagreement—evenbetweenliberals—abouttheareasoverwhichthestate hasobligations(orpermissions)tointervene.Putanotherway,thereisdisagreementoverhowmuchinterferenceandcontroloverourlivesliberalstates permissiblyexercise.Again,Ihopetobeabletosidestepmanyoftheseconcernsbynottakingtoostrongastance.Iamliberal,butIamnotconcerned herewithspecifyingexactlywhat‘flavour’ofliberal.Nonetheless,Iwillreturn tothisissueinChapter 7.

Beforemovingon,letmebrieflyreturntoortolans,dolphins, ikizukuri, andtherest.Strikingly,whilenostaterecognizesanimalrightsasendorsed inthisproject,liberalstatestypically do banmanyof(orall)thepracticesI listedearlier.IfIlivedinEuropeorNorthAmericaandIknewthatmyneighbourwasslaughteringherdogforsomeKoreancooking,orchattingwith anortolancatcheraboutsourcingbuntings,orplanningtoopenaJapanese restaurantspecializingindolphins,whales,and ikizukuri,Icouldcontactthe authorities.And,dependingonthelawsofmystate(andtheprioritiesofthe authorities…),Imightbeabletousethecoercivepowerofthestatetostop (orpunish)myneighbour.Maybe,then,animalrightsasamatterofjustice arenot too alientocontemporaryliberalsocieties.

Foodjustice

Itisworthmentioninganothersidetodiscussionsofjusticethat,regrettably, hasanambivalentrelationshipwithanimalrights: foodjustice.

Liketheliberalidealofmutualtolerationofpursuitofthegoodlife,thetraditionalconcernsoffoodjusticearecentraltothemotivationsofthisproject. Theseincludeaccesstogood,plentifulfoodforall;accesstoculturallyappropriateandimportantfoodsforthoseofminoritycommunities;availabilityof goodworkintheproductionoffoodandtheabolitionofexploitativelabour practices;theproductionoffoodinwaysrespectfultothelocalandglobal environment(andthepeoplewholiveintheseplaces);security,resilience, andindependenceinfoodproduction;andpopularandlocalcontroloffood productionanddistribution.Thesearerealissues,andreferencetothemwill appearthroughoutthebook.Butmyfocusinthissectionisnotontheissues themselves,butontherelationshipbetweenfoodjusticeandanimalrights.

Foodjusticeemergedasanoverlappingconcernofseveralactivist,scholarly,andscholar-activistcommunities.Giventhisorganicbirth,theconcept remainsrelativelylooselydefined—orperhapsa‘work-in-progress’,andone thatacademicscanmouldandinfluence(GottliebandJoshi2010,5–6).

Nonetheless,thefoodjusticeliterature,liketheliteratureonjusticeinpoliticalphilosophy,isanthropocentric,overlookingthepossibilitythatanimals, too,haveentitlementsofjustice.Atbest,thereistheoccasionalmore-or-less perfunctorynodtowards‘animalwelfare’.

Inanoverview,AlisonHopeAlkonsaysthat‘Foodjusticeresearch exploreshowracialandeconomicinequalitiesmanifestintheproduction, distribution,andconsumptionoffood,andthewaysthatcommunitiesand socialmovementsshapeandareshapedbytheseinequalities’(2012,295). Itisundeniablethattheseracialandeconomicinequalitiesaremattersof justice.Butitisfarfromclearthattheyshouldbethe only inequalitiesof concerninfood-justicescholarship.Admittedly,Alkon’saccountdoesnot precludethepossibilitythatconcernforanimalscanbe(oris)afocusof food-justiceresearch—andsheapprovinglyquotesadefinitionoffoodjusticementioninganimalwelfare.But,despiteexploringavenuesforfurther researchinfoodjustice,shedoesnotsuggestthatscholarsfurtherincorporate animals.

Indeed,Alkon—asaco-editoroftheinfluential CultivatingFoodJustice (AlkonandAgyeman2011)—sharesresponsibilityfortheanthropocentric natureoffoodjusticeresearch. CultivatingFoodJustice focusesonraceand class,andwhileseveralchaptersdiscussanimaladvocates,thisisgenerallyin thecontextofcriticizingthemfortheirinattentiontoracialinequalitiesand injustices.

Inhisexplorationoffoodjustice,KylePowysWhytedoesnotemphasize raceandclassasmuchasAlkon,buthisapproachremainshuman-focused. Hewritesthat‘Foodinjusticeoccurswhenatleastonehumangroupsystematicallydominatesoneormoreotherhumangroupsthroughtheirconnections toandinteractionswithoneanotherinlocalandglobalfoodsystems’(Whyte 2018,345).Again,thisdoesnotstrictlyimplythatanimalscannotbevictimsoffoodinjustice.Buthisrepetitionofthewordhumanperhapsindicates wherehissympathieslie.

RonaldL.Sandleroffersamoreopendefinitionoffoodjustice.Defining distributivejustice,hewritesthat‘Asystem,policyorpracticeisthoughtto beunjustifthosewhobenefitfromitdonotalsoshouldertheassociated burdens,orifthebenefitsofthesystemareunequallydistributedwithout goodreason’.Meanwhile,foodjustice‘concernstheallocationofbenefits andburdenswithinthefoodsystem’(Sandler2015,26).Hisexamplesallude toanimals,butitis(forinstance)fisherswhoarethevictimsofinjustice— notfish,whoarementionedonlyindirectly.Nonetheless,hisdefinition could captureanimals:Humansmightforceanimalstoshouldertheburdensofthe foodsystemforhumanbenefit,orfailtosharethebenefitsofthefoodsystem

withanimalswithoutgoodreason.(Assumingthatanimals’interestsmatter, thereisno might aboutit.)

Ifanimalsarerights-bearingbeingswhoimposedemandsofjusticeonus, itisreasonabletoconcludethatensuringthatthefoodsystemtreatsthem astheydeserveisamatteroffoodjustice.Itisnotmyaimheretoprovide aconcreteandall-encompassingdefinitionoffoodjustice.However,Iwill beusingtheterm.Althoughthisisnotabookofferingsustainedanalysisof raceorclass,itisabookthattakesseriouslyconcernsatthecentreoffood justiceactivismandscholarship,suchasaccesstofood,goodwork,sustainableandenvironmentallyfriendlyfoodsystems,respectforfoodcustomsand practices,andsoon.Itisalsoabookaboutjustice,andaboutfood.

Ihopethatreadersperceivethisbookasacontributiontothefoodjusticeliterature,althoughfearthatitsfocusonanimalswillbeoff-puttingto manyadvocatesoffoodjustice,whomightseeanimalrightsasadistraction fromrealmattersofjusticeatbest,oracolonialprojectatworst.Theseare contentionsthatIreject,butIreserveafulltreatmentofthisquestionfor anothertime.

Animalsandrights

Imustaddressafinalmatterbeforethisenquirycanbegininearnest.Ihave saidthatthisprojecttakesforgrantedthatanimalshaverights.ButIhave saidlittleaboutthem:whyanimalshaverights,andwhatrightstheyhave.It isworthsayingsomethingaboutbothtopicsasapreliminaryclarification— althoughanalysingpreciselywhichrightsanimalshave,andwhattheserights mean,willbeatopicthatIrevisitthroughout.Forexample,whenaddressing plant-basedmeat,wemustaskwhetherSusan Turner(2005) isrighttosay thatanimals’rightspreventusfromrepresentingthemasamereresource. Ifso,thatcouldruleplant-basedmeatoutofourrights-respectingfood system—assuming,ofcourse,plant-basedmeat does representanimalsasa mereresource.Butthisisaconversationforlater.

Followingathemeinthepoliticalturninanimalethics(Milligan2015), Itakeitthatanimalshaverightsbecausetheyarethekindsofbeingswho haveinterests.Afocusoninterest-basedrightsisexplicitinmanyworksin thepoliticalturn(e.g. Cochrane2012; Garner2013)andimplicitinmuch oftherest(e.g. DonaldsonandKymlicka2011; Meijer2019).Interest-based rightsapproachesholdthat(some)animalshaveawelfare—thingsgobetter orworseforthem.Thisisnotthesamewaythatthingsgobetterorworse foratableortree.Instead,itisaboutthequalityoftheanimal’slifefrom

thepointofviewoftheanimal—althoughwiththecaveatthatthisneednot reducesolelytowhattheanimalherselfwants,whattheanimalbelievesis inherinterest,orwhatmakestheanimalhappy.Indeed,thereisroomfor disagreementaboutwhatisinananimal’sinterests.Iwillreturntothisissue repeatedly.

Abasiclistofrightspossessedbyanimalswillincludepresumptiverights againstbeingkilledormadetosuffer(Cochrane2012)—and,wemayadd, arighttoshapethedirectionofthecommunityofwhichoneisamember (Cochrane2018).Amoreextensivesetofrightswouldentailthatwerecognizeanimals’rightstofreedom,andtoallkindsofpositiveentitlements— perhapsdeterminedbytherelationshipswehavewiththem(Donaldsonand Kymlicka2011).Indeed,afocusonthedifferentgroupsthatanimalsare membersofhasbeenakeycontributionofthepoliticalturn.(Claimsabout relationship-basedrightsmaysoundsuspect,buttheyareperfectlyfamiliar. Ihavemoreduties,includingdutiesofjustice,concerning my dogsthanI haveconcerningyours.)

Theremaybecircumstancesinwhichrightsarepermissiblyinfringed— tragiccasesofgenuineconflict,suchasthemuch-toutedsinkinglifeboator barrendesertisland,mayjustifykillinganimalsorhumans(Francione2000, chapter 7).But,generally,rightsactas‘trumps’(Dworkin1984)or‘sideconstraints’(Nozick1974,29). Trumps,becauserightstrumpotherkindsof reasonsthatmightspeakagainsttheirrespect,evenwhenthesereasonsmight otherwisebeverygood,and side-constraints asouractions,evenwhenpursuingthebestofoutcomes,areconstrainedbyrights’existence.Theyarelines that,innormalcircumstances,wemaynotcross.

Thelawdoesnotrecognizetheserights.Itshould.Asestablished,thisis abookaboutwhatastatecomplyingwithitsdutytoprotectanimalrights wouldlooklike.Itis,then,aworkof idealtheory,ratherthan non-idealtheory.Likediscussionsofjusticeinpoliticalphilosophy,thisdistinctiongoes backatleasttoPlato(see Republic 473),butowesitscurrentpopularityto Rawls(1999).Alargeandcomplexliteratureonthedistinctionbetweenideal andnon-idealtheoryhasemergedinthetwenty-firstcentury.Itwouldbe unhelpfultoreviewthishere.Instead,wecansummarizethedistinctionas simplythis:Idealtheoryisaboutwhatajustsocietywouldlooklike—itis limitedonlybytheconstraintsofpossibility.Non-idealtheoryisaboutmakingunjustsocietiesmorejust,and,ultimately,transitioningunjustsocieties tofullyjustsocieties.Itislimitedbyallthepracticalconstraintsimpacting ourpoliticalactioninthegivenunjustsocieties.

Eventhoughnon-idealtheoryistheimportantaspectofpoliticalphilosophy,asitisnon-idealtheorythatallowsustoremedyinjusticeinthereal

world,idealtheoryhasacertainpriorityovernon-idealtheory—atleast,that iswhatRawlsbelieves(1999,8).Thisisbecauseourabilitytoidentifyinjusticeandtransitiontowardsamorejustsocietyiscomparativelyminimaluntil wehaveanideaofwhatajustsocietylookslike.Considerthepresentcase. Whetherornotthezoopoliswillbeaveganstatewillmakeadifferenceto howanimalactivistscanmosteffectivelyaidanimalstoday—atleastifwe understandactivists effectivelyaidinganimals asactivistsbringingabouta worldinwhichwerealizejusticeforanimals.

Now,Iamnotclaimingthatifthezoopolisisnotvegan,weshouldnot engageinpro-veganactivism,whileifthezoopolisisvegan,allouractivism mustbepro-veganism.Philosophersdonotpresentidealtheoryaspracticalguidanceforthehereandnow,hencetheneedfornon-idealtheory. But,asIexploreinChapter 1,thisdoesnotmeanthatidealtheoryisnot usefulforbuildingbridgesintherealworld.Ifanimalactivistsandtheir mostvehementopponentscanagreeonavisionofanidealworld,thebattleishalfover.Thenon-idealconsequencesoftheidealtheoryofferedhere, naturally,warrantexploration.Iofferthebeginningsofsuchexplorationin Chapter 7—althoughsuchcommentsmustnecessarilybepreliminary.

Afinalnoteonidealtheory.Idealtheoryisnotutopianism—understood hereinthepejorativesenseofunachievable,head-in-the-cloudtheorizing. Idealtheoryisaboutcomingupwithprinciplesandinstitutionsthatwe could realize,ifonlywehadthecollectivewilltodoso.Inthegendered— andanthropocentric?—languageofJean-JacquesRousseau,itisabout‘taking menastheyareandlawsastheymightbe’(1968,49).Evenifthevision offeredinthisbookisfarfromcurrentpractice,itisonethatwecould collectivelyinstitute—ifthatiswhatwechose.

Outlineofthebook

InChapter 1,Ilayoutthemotivationforexploringanon-veganbut animal-rights-respectingstate.Ishowthattherearequestionsweshould raiseaboutveganfoodsystemsfrombothananimal-rightsandaliberalperspective.Theseare principled problems—whiletheremaybegoodpragmatic groundsforexploringnon-veganism,thesearenotmyfocus.

Theseideasinhand,Iturntoexploreindustriesthatcouldbeconsistent withanimalrights.InChapter 2,Iaddresstheprospectoffarminginvertebrates,whetherfortheirbodiesortheirproducts.Atthecoreisthequestion ofsentience.Iftheseanimalsaresentient,theyarerights-bearers,andentitled toprotection.Iftheyarenotsentient,wecanfarmthemfreely.

Difficultquestionsemergeinthecaseofanimalsaboutwhosesentience weareuncertain.And,ofcourse,ifweareunsureaboutwhetheranimalsare evensentient,gettingtothebottomofwhatisandisnotintheirinterestsis difficult.Wecannot,Isuggest,reachsimpleconclusions:Whilewecanfarm someinvertebratesfreely,somewemustfarmwithcaution,whileotherswe maynotfarmatall.

Chapter 3 turnstotheprospectofmaking‘animal’productsoutofplants, focusingonplant-basedmeats.Whilethesemightsoundinnocuous,they facecriticismfromadvocatesofveganismforsupposedlyreinforcing,rather thanchallenging,slaughter-basedanimalproducts.Andtheyfacecriticismfrombothadvocatesofplant-basedwholefoods and advocatesof slaughter-basedmeatfor,inavarietyofways,being‘bad’food.Iarguethat wecanovercomethesechallenges.

Manyofthesamechallengesarisewhenitcomestothebuddingindustryof ‘cellularagriculture’.Thisclusteroftechnologiescanproducemeat,milk,and otheranimalproductswithminimalanimalinput.Chapter 4 exploreschallengesspecifictothecellularagriculturaltechnologiesofcultivatedmeatand precisionfermentation—thelatterofwhichproduces,amongotherthings, cultivatedmilk.Thischapterthusoffersanegativecaseforcellularagriculture aspartofthefoodsystemofthezoopolis.

Chapter5stayswithcultivatedmeat,offeringapositivevisionofhowcellularagriculturalistscouldproducemeatinananimal-rights-respectingstate. Acentralpuzzleinvolveshowcellularagriculturalistssourcecells.Iargue thattheycouldsourcecellsinseveralpermissibleways.Inparticular,ifwe canreconceiveanimalsas workers,thenanimals protectedbyworkers’rights couldprovidetheneededcells.Thispossibilityallowsustoenvisionatruly idealcellularagriculture—goodforpeople and animals.

Ifanimalscanworkonfarmstoproducecells,couldtheyworkonfarms toproduceotherproducts?Inprinciple,yes—althoughslaughterhousesare outofthequestion.Asanexample,Chapter 6 lookstoeggs.Iarguethatas wellaslivingwithchickensandeatingtheireggs,peoplecouldsourceeggs fromfarmsinwhichfarmerstreatchickenswiththerespecttheywarrant. Ofcourse,thesefarmsfaceethicalchallenges—andtheycouldnotproduce cheap eggs.ButIarguethattherecouldbeaplaceforsuchfarms,andthatit islikelythattherewouldbeamarketfortheireggs.

Chapter 7 stepsbackfromquestionsaboutparticularfoodsinorderto explorethequestionofbringingaboutandmaintainingthefoodsystem thatthebookhaspointedtowards.Itexploreswhatitmeansforastateto permit and support particular(elementsof)foodsystems.Butitalsoasks whattheargumentsofthisbookmeanforactorstoday:whattheymean

Introduction 17 forindividuals’dietarychoices;forthecampaigningofactivistsandactivist organizations;forstates.

Ashortconcludingchaptersummarizestheargumentsofthebook,reflectingonwhatthebookhas,andhasnot,done.Itasksaboutwaysinwhichthe argumentcouldbeextended,andaskswhatitmeanstogetthesequestions right—and,perhapsmoreimportantly,wrong.

Thetroublewithveganism

Animaladvocatesshouldexplorethepossibilityofnon-veganfoodsystemsin thezoopolis.Indeed,thezoopolisshould(probably)permitnon-veganfood production.And,further,thezoopolisshould(probably)activelyendorseand support anon-veganfoodsystem.Atleast,thesearetheclaimsImotivatein thischapter.

Theseclaimsarecontroversial.Eventhefirstwillraiseeyebrows—solet usbeginthere.Whywouldadvocatesofanimalrightsexplorethepossibility ofnon-veganfoodsystemswhenitisanimalagriculturethathas(arguably) beenresponsibleforthemostegregiousviolationsofanimals’rights?

Animal-basedfoodsystemsarefarfromnecessary.Afterall,wedonot needtoeatanimalproductstobehealthy.Indeed,thereisempiricalevidence suggestingthatplant-basedfoodsystemswouldbehealthier.Idonotmean thissimplyinthesensethataveganfoodsystemcouldleadtolowerlevelsof certainhealthproblems—obesity,diabetes,certaincancers(see,e.g., Melina, Craig,andLevin2016)—butbecauseofthehealthbenefitsassociatedwith veganfoodsystems’environmentalcredentials(see,e.g., Scarboroughetal. 2014);withlowerriskofzoonoses(BernsteinandDutkiewicz2021; Knight etal.2021);1 andwithlowerdeploymentofantibiotics,theuseofwhich areprevalentin(intensive)animalagriculture,riskingantibioticresistance (OECD2016).

Thesegainscouldleadtosubstantialeconomicbenefits(Springmannetal. 2016; Tschofen,Azevedo,andMuller2019).Thereisevenevidencethat aplant-basedsocietywouldbesafer—areasaroundslaughterhouseshave increasedviolence,includingsexualviolence(Fitzgerald,Kalof,andDietz 2009).

Thus,notonlyisaplant-basedfoodsystempossible,butperhapsweshould desireitforreasonsbeyondanimalrights.Ifanimalshaverightsanda plant-basedsystemispossible,whyexploreanon-veganfoodsystematall?

1 WhenIfirstwrotethesewords,theworldhadnotfelttheeffectsofCOVID-19,azoonoticdisease.I believetheytakeonnewresonancenow.Nolongercanpeoplepleadignoranceordownplaythethreatof zoonoses.

Food,Justice,andAnimals.JoshMilburn,OxfordUniversityPress.©JoshMilburn(2023). DOI:10.1093/oso/9780192867469.003.0002

Iwillnotesomepragmaticreasonstoexploreanon-veganfoodsystem— althoughthesearenotmypresentfocus.Thebulkofthechapterwillsearch formoreprincipledreasonsforactivistsandtheorists—andthepolicymakers inthezoopolis—toexplore,permit,orsupportnon-veganfoodsystems.

TheconceptionofjusticeIhaveendorsedisaliberalapproachtoanimal rights.Separatingtheconceptionintoitsconstituentparts,thischapterwill exploreboth liberal and animal-rights reasonsforexploringnon-veganfood systems.Isplitliberalreasonsintotwogroups:Reasonsgroundedinrespectingdiverseconceptionsofthegood,andreasonsgroundedinthedemands offoodjustice(understoodinanthropocentricterms).Ialsogroupconcerns relatedtoanimalrightsintotwocategories.Oneconcernsharmstoanimalsinarableagriculture.Theotherconcernstheparadoxical‘extinctionist’ conclusionsofold(andnew)animalrights.

Thechapterclosesbybringingtogethertheliberalandanimal-rightscritiquesofveganism,resultinginthethreeclaimswithwhichIbegan.Each claimbuildsuponthelast,andeachismorecontroversialthanthelast.First, Iconcludethatliberaltheoristsofanimalrightsshould explore and beopen to thepossibilityofnon-veganfoodsinthezoopolis.Second,Iconcludethat thezoopolisshould,inprinciple, permit theproductionofnon-veganfoods. Andthird,mostcontroversially,Iconcludethatzoopolisshould(inprinciple,dependinguponacomplexrangeoffactors) support anon-veganfood systemif—andonlyif—suchasystemcouldbeconsistentwithrespectfor animalrights.

Pragmaticproblemswithveganism

Garnersuggeststhatthemostimportantthingpoliticalphilosophycan bringtoanimalethicsisadoseofpragmatism—amoveawayfromthe putativelyunachievablegoalsofoldanimalrights,andtowardssomething realizable(Garner2012;seealso Milligan2015; Hadley2019a).Whatmight thismean?Aplant-basedzoopoliswouldbanslaughteringanimalsforfood. Butadvocatesofanimalrightscouldsuggestthat,whateverthemeritsof thisban inprinciple,itshouldnotbeendorsed inpractice—atleastfornow (Garner2015,216).

Intheintroduction,ImentionedGarner’s pragmatic argumentsfor activismforanon-veganfoodsystem.Heendorsesanon-ideallegalsystempermittingkillinganimals,butnotmakingthemsuffer(Garner2013, chapter8).Thus,farmerscouldraisepigsandkillthemforbacon;raisechickensforeggs,killingunneededmalechicksandlessproductivehens;raise

cattleformilkandkillbullocksandoldercows.Atleast,theycould intheory.WhenGarnerexpandsonthepracticalconsequencesofhisapproach,he talksofcultivatedmeatandanimalsgeneticallyengineerednottofeelpain, worryingthateventhemostanimal-friendlyextantformsofpastoralagricultureinvolvesuffering(2013,137).Perhaps,then,thepositionheendorses isnotsopragmatic—or,jumpingahead,sofarfrommyown.

Endorsingsuffering-freeorsuffering-light animalagricultureasapragmaticstrategyiscompatiblewithmanyvisionsoftheideal,fromtheconservativetotheradical.Animalactivistssupporting(say)welfarereformand anti-crueltylegislationinpracticemighthaveprincipleddisagreementswith eachother.Meanwhile,activistswhoshareavisionoftheidealmightdisagree aboutactivistmethods.Thereisthusroomfordiscussingwhetherendorsing non-veganfoodscouldbepartofapragmaticapproachtoanimalrights.2 I returntothesequestionsinChapter 7.

Nonetheless,thesepragmaticreasonsarenotwhatinterestmehere. Instead,Iholdthatwehavegood principled reasonstoexplorenon-vegan foodsystemsasanidealtoaimfor.Thatsaid,principledcasesfornon-vegan foodsystemscouldthemselveshavepragmaticvalue.Inshort,thisisabook abouthavingourcakeandeatingittoo—orhavingour cow andeating her too.Itisabookabouthowwecanhavethebestofbothworlds;howwe canhaverespectforanimals, and accesstothepositivethingsthatanimal agriculturegivesus:Goodfood,goodjobs,andmore.

Mostofveganism’scriticsdrawingupontheprincipledreasonsforquestioningveganismexploredinthischapter—includingJocelynePorcher,Jean Kazez,andMatthewEvans,whowillbeintroducedshortly—acceptthatharm toanimalsisabadthing.Indeed,itisdifficulttofindsomeonedenyingit.3 Althoughtheiractionsmayleadustoquestiontheirsincerity,itishardto findsomeonewhodoesnotexpressregretatthesufferingcausedbyindustrialanimalagriculture.Eventhemostardentdefendersofmeatexpress regretatwhathappensinslaughterhouses,andareoftenkeentostressthis— indeed,wemightwonderaboutanyonehappywithhowslaughterhouses operate.

Allofthisistrueeveniftherearereasonstobeworriedaboutveganism. Butwhatifwecouldhaveasolutionthatrespectsanimals,butovercomesthe worriesofveganism’scritics?Evenifthisisfarfromthecurrentsituation,

2 Iamscepticaloftheclaimthatsupporting‘high-welfare’farmingisgoodforanimals,butIhave offeredpragmaticargumentsforpermitting/supportingnon-veganfoods(e.g., Milburn2016, 2018; cf. Fischer2020).

3 Therearecontrarians,whoeitherbendoverbackwardstodenythatanimalsare really harmed,orelse twistmoralargumentsuntilharminganimalsisunproblematic.

theprospectofagreementbetweenanimaladvocatesandvoracious(butreasonable)criticsofveganismissomethingthatcouldhaveimmensepragmatic value.Itoffershopeofasharedvisionofthefuture,andanantidotetohostility aroundveganisminthepubliceye.

Totakeafewheadline-grabbingexamples,vitrioltargetingvegansfrom thelikesofPiersMorgan(theprovocateurwhocalledabakerychain ‘PC-ravagedclowns’forofferingavegansausageroll)andWilliamSitwell (themagazineeditorwhojokedaboutkillingvegansinresponsetoaproposalforarticlesaboutveganism)fantheflamesofso-called‘vegaphobic’ tendencies.Meanwhile,aLeedsbutcherflailedatprotesterswithrawmeat in2018,and‘anti-vegan’protestorsfacedfinesforeatingrawsquirrelsata Londonmarketin2019.Hostilitygoesbothways,withanimalactivistssometimesoptingtousedecidedlyuncivilapproaches.Frenchactivistshavebeen handedjailtimeforproteststargetingfarmers,butchers,andrestaurateurs, withthoseinvolvedinthemeatindustrycallingforgreaterpoliceprotection. Theimageofbutcherslivinginfearfromveganattackevokesthepersonal (sometimesdisturbing)attacksassociatedwithOxfordanti-vivisectionist protestsoverseveraldecades.

Now,Idonotdeduceanythingaboutthewiderculturefromthesestark examples,andnordoIclaimanyequivalencebetweenveganandantiveganhostility.Buttheseexamplesareindicativeofadirectionthedebate could head.Itismysuggestionthatanon-vegan,althoughanimal-rightsrespecting,foodsystemoffersavisionofthefuturepalatable—more, desirable—toeveryone.Itsatisfiesanimaladvocatesasitrespectsanimalrights. Anditsatisfiescriticsofveganismbecauseitallowsthemaccesstonon-vegan foods,workwithanimals,andsoforth.

Laterinthechapter,Icometowhythispossibilityisdesirableforanimal advocates,butletusnotenowthatitissurelyprimafaciedesirablefor critics ofveganism.Itisdesirablerelativetoaveganfuture,asitallowsthemaccessto thethingsveganismclosesoff.Anditisdesirablerelativetothecurrentsituationasitallowsthemtomakegoodonclaimstoregretanimalsufferingand death.Take,forexample,MatthewEvans,afoodjournalist,chef,farmer,and apologistformeat-eating.Hesincerelybelievesthatmeathasculinaryand culturalvalue;thatworkingwithanimalsismeaningfulandimportant;that veganismmaybebadforanimals,thehungry,andothers—someofthethings exploredinthischapter.

However,Evanssupports‘minimisingharm[and]rearingfeweranimals forthesamegastronomicandnutritionalbenefit’(2019,209).Healso regretsanimaldeath:‘Thereisnothing,Irepeat nothing,niceaboutseeing awarm-bloodedanimaltakeitslastbreath’(2019,97,emphasisEvans’s).

Turn static files into dynamic content formats.

Create a flipbook
Issuu converts static files into: digital portfolios, online yearbooks, online catalogs, digital photo albums and more. Sign up and create your flipbook.
Instant download Food, justice, and animals josh milburn pdf all chapter by Education Libraries - Issuu