Instant Download Time, history, and political thought john robertson PDF All Chapters

Page 1


https://ebookmass.com/product/time-history-and-political-

Instant digital products (PDF, ePub, MOBI) ready for you

Download now and discover formats that fit your needs...

Time and History in Hegelian Thought and Spirit Sally Sedgwick

https://ebookmass.com/product/time-and-history-in-hegelian-thoughtand-spirit-sally-sedgwick/

ebookmass.com

Postsecular History: Political Theology and the Politics of Time Maxwell Kennel

https://ebookmass.com/product/postsecular-history-political-theologyand-the-politics-of-time-maxwell-kennel/

ebookmass.com

The History of Political Thought: A Very Short Introduction Richard Whatmore

https://ebookmass.com/product/the-history-of-political-thought-a-veryshort-introduction-richard-whatmore/

ebookmass.com

A Court of Debt and Deception: Shadowguard

Trials Book One

https://ebookmass.com/product/a-court-of-debt-and-deceptionshadowguard-trials-book-one-samantha-britt/

ebookmass.com

Kitchen and Bath Business and Project Management (NKBA

Professional Resource Library Book 3) 2nd Edition – Ebook PDF Version

https://ebookmass.com/product/kitchen-and-bath-business-and-projectmanagement-nkba-professional-resource-library-book-3-2nd-editionebook-pdf-version/ ebookmass.com

Oneness: East Asian Conceptions of Virtue, Happiness, and How We Are All Connected 1st Edition, (Ebook PDF)

https://ebookmass.com/product/oneness-east-asian-conceptions-ofvirtue-happiness-and-how-we-are-all-connected-1st-edition-ebook-pdf/ ebookmass.com

Analytics and Decision Support in Health Care Operations Management (Jossey Bass Public Health) 3rd Edition, (Ebook PDF)

https://ebookmass.com/product/analytics-and-decision-support-inhealth-care-operations-management-jossey-bass-public-health-3rdedition-ebook-pdf/ ebookmass.com

Uncovering Ghost (Police and Fire: Operation Alpha) (Alias Protection Book 7) Annie Miller & Operation Alpha

https://ebookmass.com/product/uncovering-ghost-police-and-fireoperation-alpha-alias-protection-book-7-annie-miller-operation-alpha/

ebookmass.com

An Introduction to Global Health Delivery 1st Edition, (Ebook PDF)

https://ebookmass.com/product/an-introduction-to-global-healthdelivery-1st-edition-ebook-pdf/ ebookmass.com

The White Witch (Love Beyond Death - The Inns Book 4)

https://ebookmass.com/product/the-white-witch-love-beyond-death-theinns-book-4-elizabeth-n-harris/

ebookmass.com

Time, History, and Political Thought

Between the cliché that ‘a week is a long time in politics’ and the aspiration of many political philosophers to give their ideas universal, timeless validity lies a gulf which the history of political thought is uniquely qualified to bridge. For what the history of political thought shows is that no conception of politics has dispensed altogether with time, and many have explicitly sought legitimacy in association with forms of history. Ranging from Justinian’s law codes to rival Protestant and Catholic visions of political community after the Fall, from Hobbes and Spinoza to the Scottish Enlightenment, and from Kant and Savigny to the legacy of German Historicism and the Algerian Revolution, this volume explores multiple ways in which different conceptions of time and history have been used to understand politics since late antiquity. Bringing together leading contemporary historians of political thought, Time, History, and Political Thought demonstrates just how much both time and history have enriched the political imagination.

John Robertson is Professor Emeritus of the History of Political Thought at the University of Cambridge and Honorary Professor of the History of Political Thought at the University of St Andrews. Previously he taught at Oxford, and he has held visiting appointments in the United States, Italy, France and China. He is a Foreign Member of the Academy of Moral and Political Sciences, Naples. His publications include The Case for the Enlightenment: Scotland and Naples 1680–1760 (2005), The Enlightenment: A Very Short Introduction (2015) and, as editor, A Union for Empire: Political Thought and the Union of 1707 (1995) and Andrew Fletcher: Political Works (1997).

Time, History, and Political Thought

University of Cambridge

Shaftesbury Road, Cambridge cb 2 8EA , United Kingdom

One Liberty Plaza, 20th Floor, New York, NY 10006, USA

477 Williamstown Road, Port Melbourne, VIC 3207, Australia

314–321, 3rd Floor, Plot 3, Splendor Forum, Jasola District Centre, New Delhi – 110025, India

103 Penang Road, #05–06/07, Visioncrest Commercial, Singapore 238467

Cambridge University Press is part of Cambridge University Press & Assessment, a department of the University of Cambridge.

We share the University’s mission to contribute to society through the pursuit of education, learning and research at the highest international levels of excellence.

www.cambridge.org

Information on this title: www.cambridge.org/9781009289368

DOI : 10.1017/9781009289399

© Cambridge University Press & Assessment 2023

This publication is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception and to the provisions of relevant collective licensing agreements, no reproduction of any part may take place without the written permission of Cambridge University Press & Assessment.

First published 2023

A catalogue record for this publication is available from the British Library

A Cataloging-in-Publication data record for this book is available from the Library of Congress

ISBN 978-1-009-28936-8 Hardback

Cambridge University Press & Assessment has no responsibility for the persistence or accuracy of URLs for external or third-party internet websites referred to in this publication and does not guarantee that any content on such websites is, or will remain, accurate or appropriate.

Contributors

George Garnett  is Professor of Medieval History at the University of Oxford, and Fellow and Tutor in History at St Hugh’s College. He has published several books on the Norman Conquest, most recently the first volume of a study of its significance in English History through to the eighteenth century. He also works on Continental political and legal thought in the middle ages and early modern period.

Aaron Garrett  is Professor of Philosophy at Boston University. His books include Meaning in Spinoza’s Method (Cambridge, 2003) and Scottish Philosophy in the Eighteenth Century, co-edited with James Harris (Oxford, 2015). He is presently writing a monograph on the rise of modern moral philosophy entitled The Making of Modern Moral Philosophy.

Kinch Hoekstra  is Chancellor’s Professor of Political Science and Law at the University of California, Berkeley, and an affiliated Professor in Philosophy and Classics. He was previously a member of the Faculties of Philosophy and Classics at the University of Oxford. He is the author of studies on ancient, Renaissance and early modern political thought, and co-editor of The Oxford Handbook of Hobbes (2016). He is currently co-editing Hobbes’ translation of Thucydides for the Clarendon Edition of the Works of Thomas Hobbes.

Caroline Humfress  is Professor of Medieval History and Director of the Institute of Legal and Constitutional Research at the University of St Andrews. She has published widely on late antique history, particularly in relation to law, legal orderings and religious beliefs and practices. She is especially interested in dialogue between historians, legal anthropologists, sociologists and modern legal theorists. Recent publications include ‘Beyond the (Byzantine) State: Towards a User Theory of Jurisdiction’ in Nico Krisch, ed., Entangled Legalities Beyond the State (Cambridge, 2021).

Charlotte Johann is Junior Research Fellow at Churchill College, Cambridge. She works at the intersection of legal, political and intellectual history, exploring how conflicting visions of legal order impacted on the theory and practice of politics

in the long nineteenth century. In addition to published articles, she is preparing a monograph on the historical jurisprudence of Friedrich Carl von Savigny and its role in shaping legal politics in nineteenth-century Germany.

Emma Stone Mackinnon is University Assistant Professor in the History of Modern Political Thought at the University of Cambridge and a Fellow of Emmanuel College. She has published on twentieth-century political thought, political theory, and the history of human rights and humanitarianism.

Chris Meckstroth  is Associate Professor of the History of Political Thought at the University of Cambridge. He taught previously at Harvard and the University of Chicago. He is the author of The Struggle for Democracy: Paradoxes of Progress and the Politics of Change (Oxford, 2015). His work treats the history and theory of popular government and the challenges it raised for political thought in the nineteenth century.

Sarah Mortimer  is Associate Professor of Early Modern History at the University of Oxford, and Student and Tutor in History at Christ Church, Oxford. She is interested in the intersections of ethics, politics and religion across early modern European thought, publishing extensively on these themes: most recently, her book, Reformation, Resistance and Reason of State 1517–1625 (Oxford, 2021).

John Robertson  is Professor Emeritus of the History of Political Thought at the University of Cambridge, and an Emeritus Fellow of Clare College; he is also Honorary Professor of the History of Political Thought at St Andrews University. He has published on a range of topics in intellectual history in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, in particular Enlightenment, both the concept and its manifestations in Scotland and in Naples. He is currently writing a study of sacred history and its contribution to thinking about society and state between 1650 and 1800.

Magnus Ryan is Associate Professor in History at the University of Cambridge, and a Fellow of Peterhouse, Cambridge. His interests extend across Roman, Feudal and Canon Law and their relation to political thinking from late antiquity to the seventeenth century, leading to a series of articles on these themes. Most recently he has prepared (with George Garnett) a new translation and edition of works of Bartolus of Sassoferrato, forthcoming with Cambridge University Press.

Silvia Sebastiani is Professor of Early Modern History at the École des Hautes Études en Sciences Sociales in Paris. A specialist of the Scottish Enlightenment, she works on the questions of race, gender, animality and history writing. She is the author of The Scottish Enlightenment. Race, Gender, and the Limits of Progress (Basingstoke and New York, 2013 – Italian edition, Bologna, 2008) and the co-author, with JeanFrédéric Schaub, of Race et histoire dans les sociétés occidentales (15e–18e siècle) (Paris, 2021). She is completing a book on the boundaries of humanity in the Enlightenment, focusing on how the great apes contributed to the shaping of human and social sciences.

Quentin Skinner  was Regius Professor of History at the University of Cambridge from 1996 to 2008, and since then has been Barber Beaumont Professor of the Humanities at Queen Mary University of London. He is the author of numerous books on political theory and modern intellectual history.

Waseem Yaqoob  is Lecturer in the History of Political Thought at Queen Mary University of London. His interests span thinking about politics, economics and international order in the twentieth century. His book, History and Judgement: the Political Thought of Hannah Arendt, is under contract with Princeton University Press.

Acknowledgements

As editor, I am grateful first of all to my contributors, with whom it has been a pleasure to collaborate. Not only have they been willing to bring their expertise to the specific subject of the volume, they have been no less willing to engage with my conception of what it might achieve, and to respond to my editorial suggestions for the development of their chapters. For their part, Caroline Humfress, Sarah Mortimer, Silvia Sebastiani and Quentin Skinner have at various points also given me good editorial counsel. All the contributors have been by turns resilient and patient, some in the face of serious adversity, the Covid-induced circumstances of the past three years having been disruptive in ways that individuals and institutions could not have predicted. For these qualities, too, I am thankful. Protracted as they have been, the discussions between us have been exemplary of collegial scholarship. But the volume would not exist without the encouragement, assistance and counsel of its Press editor, Elizabeth Friend-Smith, a consistent friend to and supporter of the history of political thought in Cambridge and beyond. We are also greatly indebted to the two readers for the Press, one who remains anonymous, the other, Sophie Smith, who has volunteered her identity. Both took the trouble to see the point of the volume, the greatest of encouragements to the editor as well as the basis for their many constructive suggestions. Further thanks are owed to Elliot Beck and Chris Hudson at the Press, to Melanie James for helpful copyediting, and to Thirumangai Thamizhmani for her timely management of the production process. Behind the volume lay a conference, Political Thought, Time, and History, held at Clare College, Cambridge on 10/11 May 2018. All but one of the contributors here spoke at the conference, where they were joined by Sir Christopher Clark, David D’Avray and Shruti Kapila. I am grateful to all three for their papers, powerful and apposite, and to Shruti Kapila in particular for her willingness to contribute to the volume, until peculiarly adverse circumstances made that impossible. While this volume would have been richer for a contribution on ‘Time in Indian political thought’, the subject might very well receive a volume to itself. I am likewise grateful to Annabel Brett, Megan Donaldson and Sylvana Tomaselli for closing the conference with a roundtable that not only engaged with the papers, but

looked beyond them to directions in which the conference theme might be taken in future. As chairs and in other ways, Sophie Lunn-Rockliffe, Annabel Brett, Richard Serjeantson, Tom Pye, Duncan Kelly, Kenzie Bok, Charlotte Johann, Eloise Davies and Hester van Hensbergen provided the conference with leadership and co-ordination throughout. Around 100 conference delegates provided the best of audiences, repeatedly asking questions relevant and constructive; I am particularly grateful to those who travelled a distance to be there, among them Elsbeth Heaman, Paschalis Kitromilides, Li Hongtu, and Shannon Stimson. Conference organisation was made much easier and more enjoyable by many staff in both Clare College and the Cambridge History Faculty. Finally, and not least, funding which made the conference possible was provided by the Cambridge Centre for Political Thought and the Faculty of History’s Trevelyan Fund. I am very grateful to both, and especially to David Runciman, benefactor as well as first Director of the Centre.

Behind that conference lay another, History, Politics, Law, held at Clare College in 2016, organised by Annabel Brett, Megan Donaldson and Martti Koskenniemi, which provided a model and inspiration.1 It is a pleasure to record my gratitude to Annabel Brett for discussion of the two conferences, which gave me a sharper sense of the questions this volume should seek to address.

Finally, I take this opportunity to thank John G. A. Pocock, great historian of political thought, who has thought about the themes of conference and volume longer and harder than any of us, for the stimulus of his writings, his correspondence and his conversation.

Precisely because of the extent and depth of my debts, however, it is all the more essential to state that responsibility for shortcomings in what I myself have contributed to the volume, and for all editorial decisions, is mine alone.

1 As also the volume which ensued: Annabel Brett, Megan Donaldson and Martti Koskenniemi, eds., History, Politics, Law. Thinking through the International (Cambridge, 2021).

Note on References and the Bibliography

Footnote references for each chapter provide full details of author, title, place and date of publication at first mention, thereafter author surname and short title only. Unless otherwise indicated, the final numbers are page references (without p. or pp); where there may be ambiguity, p. or pp. are inserted. All references are then collected in the unified Bibliography, which also provides the name of the publisher, where identified.

Within the Bibliography are listed many of the works – books, collaborative volumes and articles – which have inspired or made important contributions to the current discussion of the roles of history and the significance of temporality in the study of politics. But the Bibliography is not comprehensive in its coverage of this literature, an ambition which would have required a separate research exercise –and would almost immediately have become out of date.

Introduction: Time, History, and Political Thought

Among statements of the obvious, few are likely to seem more obvious than that politics takes place in time and is subject to history. At its most banal – Harold Wilson’s ‘a week is a long time in politics’1 – it has become a cliché. But it is also the premise of some of the most classic texts in the canon of Western political thought. Preeminent examples are Machiavelli’s The Prince and Discourses, where he argued that the key to success in politics, whether for individual rulers or for republics, lay in adapting to and taking advantage of time and circumstances. Alternatively, others have argued that politics will only be understood when recognised as subject to long-term economic and social forces: in this way, Hegel and Marx argued, politics served history’s purposes. Yet time and again – just as obviously – political thought has sought to escape the confines of time and history, and to present its findings as timeless, of universal application. If anything texts in this vein are even more classic, stretching as they do from Plato’s Republic in antiquity to John Rawls’ A Theory of Justice in the late twentieth century, by way of More’s Utopia, Hobbes’ Leviathan and the 1948 Universal Declaration of Human Rights.

It is not hard to see why a universal, timeless vision of politics should appeal: what humans have in common should trump their differences, and all should enjoy security, justice and equal rights. But again, the reverse is not hard to accept either. For notwithstanding those imputed commonalities, the historical record has repeatedly proved recalcitrant. Peoples, whether organised in states or connected by looser forms of association, have stubbornly asserted their political differences, appealing to the past or simply to current circumstances to justify their particularity. In the face of this binary, the standard scholarly response is to be more discriminating – to

For critical comments on drafts of this introduction, as well as many suggestions and references, I am most grateful to Annabel Brett, Blake Ewing, Charlotte Johann, Sarah Mortimer, Silvia Sebastiani and both the anonymous reader and Sophie Smith, as readers for Cambridge University Press.

1 Harold Wilson (1916–1995), Labour Party prime minister of the United Kingdom 1964–1970, 1974–1976; the remark is thought to have been first made in 1964.

draw more distinctions in order to show that a simple opposition between the temporal and historical and the timeless and universal is too simple.

A first, crucial step is to recognise that time and history are separable concepts. Time is a concept no political theory can be without altogether. It is essential even to Hobbes’ ‘natural condition of mankind’, where the crucial incentive to war between humans is fear of what others will do. Moreover while ‘time’ can be measured as uniform – clock time – it can be conceptualised in very different ways according to perspective of the thinker or the object of enquiry, yielding distinct ‘temporalities’, or time regimes. In one view of politics, a week is a long time; in another, not at all. The temporality of politics conceived as a form of social organisation, for example, is unlikely to correspond with that of revolutions; and different systems of law are likely to have distinct temporalities.

For an argument to be historical, by contrast, it must appeal to some record of human experience, a documentary or material residue from which historians can reconstruct what they suppose happened ‘in fact’. A historical political argument is one which refers, explicitly or by allusion, to such ‘facts’, or to the narratives by which historians have connected them. The distinction was clearly drawn by Rousseau, in the prologue to the Discourse on the Origin of Inequality among Men (1755), in which he began by ‘setting aside all the facts’, in favour of ‘hypothetical and conditional reasonings, better suited to elucidate the Nature of things’. The account he proceeded to give of original, natural human equality was unavoidably temporal, but made no appeal even to what Rousseau took to be the oldest recorded history, that of the Bible.2 A further complication is that the histories of interest to political thinkers have been of more than one kind. What is assumed to be the most relevant and most cited form of history in European political thought is the classical narrative, devoted to war, diplomacy and power struggles within communities, and exemplified by Herodotus and Thucydides, Livy and Tacitus, and later by Guicciardini and Gibbon. But political thought has also emerged from and engaged with many other kinds of history, including sacred, legal, social and natural history. The different kinds of history have in turn been informed by contrasting assumptions about how events or more structural developments unfold, whether cyclically or in a linear, progressive or even purposive direction, and by the ascription of different temporal rhythms or durations (short, medium or long) to the layers of human activity.

Time and its temporalities, history and the narratives by which it is told, thus form a triad with political thought, the weightings of whose components are constantly shifting. Political thinkers may often have sought refuge from the constraints of time and history in the universal; but none has dispensed altogether with temporality,

2 Jean-Jacques Rousseau, Discours sur l’origine et les fondemens de l’inégalité parmi les hommes, in Œuvres complètes III Du contrat social, Écrits politiques, ed. B. Gagnebin and M. Raymond, Bibliothèque de la Pléiade (Paris, 1964), 132–3. Translation by Victor Gourevitch, The Discourses and other early political writings (Cambridge, 1997), 132. Although as Silvia Sebastiani points out in Chapter 9 in this volume, Rousseau proceeded to let ‘the facts’ back in through his notes.

and even the most determined to exclude history have known that it will still be camped at theory’s gates.

Among political scientists, time is now taken ever more seriously as a dimension of politics.3 For their part, historians of political thought have certainly not neglected either time or history in reconstructing their subject: the quantity of references to work which engages with them, both in this introduction and in the substantive chapters to follow, testifies the contrary. Yet there is a case for suggesting that these dimensions of political thought might profitably be paid more attention. One barrier to doing so may derive from what is otherwise a strength of the history of political thought: its proximity to political theory and political philosophy as they are currently practised. As Annabel Brett puts it, it is an inherent feature of the history of political thought that its very concern with the ‘political’ ‘pulls’ it into political thought itself, and hence into its present concerns.4 The pull is liable to be felt most naturally and urgently by historians of recent political thought. The closer they are to the present, the easier it becomes for them to contribute to discussion of the issues whose genesis they have been studying: a theoretical pay-off from historical enquiry is visibly within reach. But the same pull may affect the history of political thought of any period, shaping its narratives to yield implications of relevance to the present. There is nothing inherently wrong in this tendency: the scope to make a theoretical or philosophical contribution is what distinguishes the history of political thought of any period from other forms of historical enquiry. Nevertheless, a problem arises if the present concerns of political theory or philosophy over-determine understanding of the roles temporality and history have played in past political thinking.

The problem is not that the theorist or philosopher may have a natural preference for the universal to the neglect of the historical. If anything, the greater danger is the opposite: a reductive temptation to use history as a ‘reality check’, exposing the illusions within the languages and the concepts deployed by those in power to legitimate their rule. In this guise, history is treated as external to theory and a test of its usage. Cast as ‘political realism’, this is a powerful instrument of critique. It draws inspiration from classic historical treatments of politics, not least the ‘steely realism’ of Thucydides. But its sharpest edge is turned to the present, where it has been applied with telling effect to undercut the liberal universalism of Rawls’ theory of justice. Within a decade of its publication, it is argued, a theory of justice designed

3 As a sample: Paul Pierson, Politics in Time. History, Institutions and Social Analysis (Princeton and Oxford, 2004); Elizabeth F. Cohen, The Political Value of Time. Citizenship, Duration, and Democratic Justice (Cambridge, 2018); Klaus H. Goetz, ed., The Oxford Handbook of Time and Politics (Oxford, online publication 2021). DOI 10 1093/oxfordhb/9780190862084 013 35

4 Annabel Brett, ‘Between history, politics and law: history of political thought and history of international law’, in Annabel Brett, Megan Donaldson and Martti Koskenniemi, eds., History, Politics, Law. Thinking through the International (Cambridge, 2021), 19–48, at 21. I am indebted to the author for the opportunity to read this paper before its publication: its conception of what is distinctive to the history of political thought has shaped the argument of this introduction.

to be proof against historical change and even to shield its subjects from the future had been rendered anachronistic by the reality of economic crisis.5 The problem here is that a politics which appeals to history as its external arbiter is also its narrator, telling a story which it anticipates its readers will accept. The critical advantages of such a ‘realist’ historical perspective are less apparent in the study of earlier periods, where the reconstruction of ‘reality’ is less intuitive, and the thinkers’ own conceptions of time and history may seem remote from ours. In that longer perspective, it becomes clearer that to oppose history to theory in the name of a reality check is to miss how political theories have themselves constructed time and history, and how the histories so constructed (and their accompanying temporalities) have enabled different visions of political life. While no historian of political thought can (or should) deny the pull of the present, the resort to history in the name of realism is liable to curtail rather than facilitate enquiry into how relations between politics, time, and history have been conceived.

Even as some tendencies within political theory may be narrowing the space for time and history, however, the study of history itself has been undergoing what has been characterised as a ‘temporal turn’. Predicated on the emergence of a new conception of ‘History’, the temporal turn has potentially far-reaching implications for the understanding of ‘modern’ politics. The inspiration for this ‘turn’ has been the thinking of the German historian and philosopher of history Reinhart Koselleck, as developed in a succession of essays between the 1960s and the 1990s.6 In outline, Koselleck’s thesis was as follows. Between 1750 and 1850, a period Koselleck initially and influentially labelled the Sattelzeit, literally ‘saddle time’, there was a transformation in what Europeans understood by ‘history’. Before 1750, time was taken to be stable, so that history followed a cyclical pattern. What had happened in war and politics was recorded in histories (Historie), and precisely because time was recursive, these histories also served as exemplars of military and political conduct, historia magistra vitae. By 1850, however, ‘History’ (Geschichte) was understood to possess a conceptual identity separate from the works in which it was written, and to pursue a linear, progressive course of development, in which time was accelerating.

5 As in Raymond Geuss, History and Illusion in Politics (Cambridge, 2001); and in more compelling detail, Katrina Forrester, In the Shadow of Justice. Postwar Liberalism and the Remaking of Political Philosophy (Princeton and Oxford, 2019); see esp. 172–203, on the contortions required for Rawls to shield his subjects from a concern with the future. For comment on varieties of realism: Bonnie Honig and Marc Stears, ‘The new realism: from modus vivendi to justice’, in J. Floyd and M. Stears, eds., Political Philosophy versus History? (Cambridge, 2011), 177–205; and on ‘exposure’ as its default trope: Brett, ‘Between history, politics and law’, 34.

6 The initial set of essays was published in German in 1979 and translated into English by Keith Tribe as Futures Past. On the Semantics of Historical Time (Cambridge, MA and London, 1985). There have been two further translated collections which do not correspond directly to German originals: The Practice of Conceptual History: Timing History, Spacing Concepts, by Todd S. Presner et al. (Stanford, 2002) and Sediments of Time. On Possible Histories, by Sean Franzel and Stefan-Ludwig Hoffmann (Stanford, 2018). References to specific essays later in this volume.

At the centre of this transformation lay the French Revolution, which had engendered a new idea of political possibility, revolution as the overthrow of existing social relations, and a new ‘horizon of expectation’, in which the prospect of radical change was the political norm. Koselleck compared the new sense of revolutionary expectation to that of Christian eschatology, anticipating the end of the world; reinvigorated by the Reformation, eschatology had been the main threat to the stability of time in the pre-modern world. But after the French Revolution the anticipation was of transformation in this world, gradually extending across the globe. To the new conception of ‘History’ it had been easy to attach normative purpose: history could confidently be equated with progress towards a chosen goal, whether freedom, nation-statehood, socialism or communism. Such, Koselleck argued, was the history and temporality of the Neuzeit, a term readily translated into English as ‘modernity’.

Since the early 2000s, Koselleck’s thesis has stimulated an intensifying debate among historians, diffusing the idea of a ‘temporal turn’ in the discipline. An important early intervention was made by the French historiographer François Hartog. Detecting disillusion with modernity, Hartog diagnosed the cause as a pervasive ‘presentism’ which views the past as a subject for commemoration rather than critical understanding and a basis for political action. In response, he proposed that historians think in terms of ‘regimes of historicity’, which would allow for different historical paths to modernity.7 More recently, Hartog has returned to the problem of presentism, connecting it to a loss of expectation in a future threatened by climate change. Modifying his earlier response, Hartog now suggests a return to thinking of time simply as Chronos, abandoning the temporality of Kairos, or expectation, which Christianity took over from the Greeks and used to characterise the period of waiting for the final Krisis of Christ’s return. Modernity’s ‘horizon of expectation’, Hartog would seem to be arguing, should be sacrificed to the crisis of the Anthropocene, leaving lineal time, accounted for by chronology, as the least threatening temporality in which to comprehend climate change.8 Hartog’s theses have in turn stimulated debate in their own right, notably in the collection edited by Marek Tamm and Laurent Olivier, Rethinking Historical Time (2019).9

Others have sought to apply insights deriving from the temporal turn to the politics of the past. Notable among these has been Christopher Clark, whose Time and Power (2019) examines the contrasting attitudes to historical temporality adopted by

7 François Hartog, Régimes d’historicité. Présentisme et expériences du temps (Paris, 2003), translated by Saskia Brown as Regimes of Historicity. Presentism and Experiences of Time (New York, 2015). For a similar lament over ‘presentism’, Hans Ulrich Gumbrecht, Our Broad Present: Time and Contemporary Culture (New York, 2014).

8 François Hartog, ‘Chronos, Kairos, Krisis: the genesis of western time’, History and Theory, 60:3 (2021), 425–39, with a series of responses, 440–68.

9 Marek Tamm and Laurent Olivier, eds., Rethinking Historical Time, New Approaches to Presentism (London and New York, 2019). For an argument convergent with Hartog’s rehabilitation of chronology, Helge Jordheim, ‘Return to chronology’, at 43–56.

four German regimes since the seventeenth century, those of Frederick William the Great Elector, Frederick II, Bismarck, and the Third Reich. Taking cues from both Koselleck and Hartog, Clark exchanged the terms of the latter’s concept to focus on the ‘historicity of regimes’, to yield a study of ‘chronopolitics’, or how understandings of time and change shape political decision-making.10 A similar interest motivates the collection with the reversed title Power and Time (2020), edited by Dan Edelstein, Stefanos Geroulanos and Natasha Wheatley, although they prefer the term ‘chronocenosis’ to capture the potential for conflict between different political and legal temporalities.11 The appeal of the ‘temporal turn’ is clear, but as the proliferation of ‘chrono’-concepts perhaps implies, its outcomes are still open.

As Edelstein and others suggest, there is no reason why the temporal turn should not also stimulate fresh thinking about time and history in the history of political thought. To do so, however, requires returning to the theses of Koselleck on which the turn was founded, since these provided not only a re-conception of ‘History’ but a new approach to the history of modern political thought. For this purpose, the next section (2) of this introduction will look more closely at Koselleck’s account of the politics of ‘modern’ time, examining both the intellectual history through which it was demonstrated, and the meta-historical assumptions required to sustain it. The potential of Koselleck’s history, it will be argued, is evident in his account of the new temporality of revolution; but the thesis as a whole remains hostage to an over-determined concept of ‘modernity’.

Instead of developing the Koselleckian version of the temporal turn, therefore, I argue in the following section (3) that historians of political thought would do better to harness the methodological and historiographical resources which already exist within their discipline. In particular, I shall return to the suggestion that political thought is best studied through its languages rather than its concepts. As John Pocock has sought to demonstrate, thinking in terms of languages is particularly well adapted to grasping the different ways in which time and history have been put to work in political thought. While a single volume cannot cover every possible way of doing so, the subsequent section (4) will identify as many as six forms of temporal–historical political thinking which are the subject of contributions later in this collection. Each of these will be outlined, and the specific contributions to this volume introduced by their relation to them. As I emphasise in conclusion (5), the resulting picture of the ways in which time, history, and politics have been interrelated is necessarily selective; others might be added. Nevertheless, what is covered in this volume is already much richer than what is suggested by a focus on the

10 Christopher Clark, Time and Power. Visions of History in German Politics from the Thirty Years’ War to the Third Reich (Princeton and Oxford, 2019). The Introduction provides a densely referenced account of the ‘temporal turn’. For ‘chronopolitics’, 14 and note 36.

11 Dan Edelstein, Stefanos Geroulanos and Natasha Wheatley, eds., Power and Time. Temporalities in Conflict and the Making of History (Chicago and London, 2020).

advent of the ‘modern’ alone, while demonstrating that history can serve many more purposes for political thinkers than a simple reality check. Rather, the contributions to this volume demonstrate how rich and varied have been the possibilities opened for political thought by different conceptions of time and history.

2

The essentials of Koselleck’s account of the accelerating time of ‘modernity’ have already been sketched above. But there was more to that account than the standard summary reveals; to test its significance for the history of political thought, both the story he was telling and its particular conceptual character need amplification. The story recounted in the essays collected in Futures Past and successor volumes is clearly connected to the one he had told in his first book, originally published in 1959, and eventually translated as Critique and Crisis. Enlightenment and the Pathogenesis of Modern Society. 12 There Koselleck had characterised Enlightenment philosophy as an expression of frustration with the absolutist state, and with the Hobbesian principles by which absolutism was justified. Designed to enable the sovereign to enforce toleration and prevent the renewal of religious war, the Hobbesian concept of the state had stood in the way of the philosophes’ aspirations for radical social and political change. In response, the philosophes and their German counterparts, the Illuminati, had put morals before politics, and articulated their goals in the abstract, utopian terms of natural law. On this basis, they envisaged an undermining of the absolutist state, a prognosis of revolution which they concealed within a philosophy of history as progress. Combining these intellectual commitments with an approach to politics modelled on the secretive rituals of Freemasonry, the ‘prophètes philosophes’ of the Enlightenment had successfully precipitated the overthrow of the ancien régime.

In that first book, Koselleck was telling a certain story, one with obvious echoes of Tocqueville’s L’ancien régime et la révolution (1856), and even of the CounterRevolutionary thesis of a ‘philosophe conspiracy’ (in its French and German versions). Intellectual responsibility for the French Revolution was attributed to a utopian willingness to slight the role of the state in maintaining order, in favour of a transformation of society in the name of moral absolutes. It was this story which informed Koselleck’s essay ten years later on ‘Historical criteria of the modern concept of revolution’, which contended that after 1789 the idea of ‘revolution’ had become a ‘collective singular’, uniting in itself the course of all the individual revolutions that followed the French. Built into this modern concept of revolution were both an acceleration of political time and, through declarations of rights, the

12 Reinhart Koselleck, Critique and Crisis. Enlightenment and the Pathogenesis of Modern Society (Oxford, New York and Hamburg, 1988), trans. of Kritik und Krise. Eine Studie zur Pathogenese der bürgerlichen Welt (Freiburg and Munich, 1959).

expectation that political and social revolution would coincide. Further features of the concept included the implication that it would be global in ambition and ‘permanent’ until that ambition had been realised.13 Koselleck connected the new concept with the transformation by which History itself had become singular, formalising the junction he had identified in the minds of the philosophes between a prognosis of revolution and a philosophy of history. Triggering a new sense of accelerating time, the experience of revolution had reinforced the idea that History could be progressive and purposive in its own right.14 Koselleck was reluctant to identify this concept of ‘History’ with ‘Historicism’, perhaps to avoid associating it with the historiographical story told by Meinecke, among others;15 but at this stage he, too, was clearly advancing claims that belong within the history of political thought and historiography.

As such, evidence to substantiate Koselleck’s claims could be sought in the writings of individual thinkers: examples were his discussions of the political thinking of Lorenz von Stein (1815–1890), and of the historical philosophy of J. C. Chladenius (1710–1759) and his German successors down to Hegel.16 But the focus of his historical study was not authors, texts, or even languages; it was concepts. The history of concepts, Begriffsgeschichte, realised in the multi-volume, collaborative lexicon edited with Otto Brunner and Werner Conze, entitled the Geschichtliche Grundbegriffe (1972–1997), was given the task of demonstrating the wholesale intellectual transformation of political and historical thinking which Koselleck was convinced had taken place between 1750 and 1850. Its ‘central problematic’, Koselleck wrote in his Introduction to Volume I, ‘is the dissolution of the old society of orders and estates, and the development of the modern world. … Its research is meant to reveal what is distinctively modern about the way we conceptualise political and social life.’17 As successive volumes of the lexicon appeared, Koselleck clarified the possibilities of the methodology: in particular there was no supposition that concepts were fixed in meaning. Conceptual history was as much concerned with concepts’ diachronic development as with their synchronic articulation. Concepts might have their own, or indeed more than one, temporality. In the layering of temporalities lay the possibility, much emphasised by Koselleck, of the ‘simultaneity of the nonsimultaneous’, the opportunity for conceptual usages from different times, or which implied different temporalities of implementation, to be combined in a specific

13 Koselleck, ‘Historical criteria of the modern concept of revolution’ (original publication in German in 1969), Futures Past, 39–54.

14 Koselleck, ‘Modernity and the planes of historicity’ (1968), Futures Past, 3–20.

15 See Chapter 12 later in this volume, Waseem Yaqoob, ‘After Historicism’, 274–77, for an assessment of Koselleck’s relation to this tradition.

16 ‘Historical prognosis in Lorenz von Stein’s Essay on the Prussian Constitution’ (1965), ‘Perspective and temporality: a contribution to the historiographical exposure of the historical world’ (1977), Futures Past, 57–69, 130–55.

17 Reinhart Koselleck, ‘Introduction and Prefaces to the Geschichtliche Grundbegriffe’, translated by Michaela Richter, Contributions to the History of Concepts, 6:1 (2011), 1–37, quotation at 8.

political present.18 For all the methodological sophistication of conceptual history, however, its deployment was predicated on an explicit periodisation: its subject was the history of the political thought of modern times.19

For Koselleck this was by no means only a matter of intellectual history. Keen to align Begriffsgeschichte with the new social history of the 1960s,20 Koselleck argued that the modern understanding of time had derived from a broader social experience. Underpinning this claim was a concept of ‘experience’ as informed by ‘reality’, which exists independently of and prior to language, and which language is always struggling to master.21 Thus he argued that the political experience of the French Revolution had been reinforced by the industrial revolution, specifically the discovery and diffusion of steam power. It was ‘technological–industrial progress’ which had ‘denaturalized’ time, transforming it into a generalised experience of acceleration. The time of the Neuzeit, of ‘modernity’, therefore, was not simply an intellectual construction; it was a social mentality, which made it possible for all to share in the political expectations associated with revolution, on a global scale.22

There was still another, explicitly ‘metahistorical’, layer to Koselleck’s argument, underpinning both experience and language. This he characterised as ‘historical anthropology’. It covered the three ‘anthropological pregivens’ of human experience: the lifecycle of birth and death, the distinction between ‘insiders’ and ‘outsiders’, and the hierarchy of above and below, exemplified by the master–slave relationship. These were the conditions of all possible human histories, circumscribing the scope of linguistic representation.23 Likewise metahistorical were two concepts of Koselleck’s own coining, which were not attributed to the Sattelzeit, but which were crucial to his explanation of what happened during that period: the ‘space of experience’ and the ‘horizon of expectation’. The ‘space of experience’ comprises the totality of past times; when time is regular (before it began to accelerate), the space

18 Koselleck, ‘Introduction to the GG’, 16–22; also ‘Sediments of time’ (Zeitschichten) (1994), Sediments of Time, 3–9. See also the comments by Keith Tribe, ‘Intellectual history as Begriffsgeschichte’, in Richard Whatmore and Brian Young, eds., A Companion to Intellectual History (Chichester, 2016), 61–71, on the extent to which realisation of the aims of the GG depended on the availability of contributors and the time they could devote to research.

19 The extent to which the periodisation of the modern is at odds with the concept of multiple temporalities is debated by commentators: Helge Jordheim, ‘Against periodization: Koselleck’s theory of multiple temporalities’, History and Theory, 51:2 (2012), 151–71; Juhan Hellerma, ‘Koselleck on modernity, Historik, and layers of time’, History and Theory, 59:2 (2020), 188–209; also Sabina Loriga, ‘Préface à la nouvelle edition’, Reinhart Koselleck, Le futur passé (Paris, 2015), 7–23.

20 Koselleck, ‘Begriffsgeschichte and social history’ (1972), Futures Past, 73–91.

21 Koselleck, ‘Linguistic change and the history of events’ (1989), Sediments of Time, 137–57. Consistent with this, Koselleck explicitly rejected the methodologies of ‘meaning and experience’, ‘text and ‘context’ which give priority to language, 137.

22 Koselleck, ‘Does history accelerate?’ (first delivered, 1976; first published, 1985), Sediments of Time, 79–99, esp. 82–93.

23 Koselleck, ‘Linguistic change’, Sediments of Time, 138–41, 151.

of experience ‘leaps over time’. Once time was experienced as accelerating, however, that space was superseded: there was a new, constantly expanding ‘horizon of expectation’, which refused to be confined to the space of experience. This was the time of modernity, the temporality which made it possible to conceptualise a political expectation of permanent, global revolution.24

Koselleck’s thesis concerning the time and politics of the Neuzeit, therefore, was a multi-layered construction: what began as an intellectual–historical narrative was re-told through histories of selected concepts, underpinned by a claim about a larger economic and social reality, and framed with the aid of metahistorical propositions derived from anthropological pre-givens. Much more than a history, it was a ‘Theory’, a philosophy of History.25 What the thesis did not have was any positive normative implication. On the contrary, Koselleck insisted in a late essay, the progressive purposes ascribed to ‘History’ in the nineteenth century had been exposed as meaningless, if not absurd, by the events of the twentieth. For Germany in particular, the outcome of ‘modern’ history had been the catastrophe of the two world wars, whose normative meaninglessness was epitomised by the battles of Verdun and Stalingrad, and its normative absurdity by the Holocaust.26 But Koselleck did not want to tie his argument exclusively to the German context. The legacy of the Neuzeit, of modernity in general, of its accelerating temporality and its politics of revolutionary expectation, was a positive absence of value. Consistent with this, Koselleck distanced himself sharply from intellectual historians who supposed that study of past thought involved engagement with moral choices.27

The starkness of this conclusion seems to have been ignored by the majority of historians interested in his thesis of the accelerating time of modernity. This may be explained by a desire to get away from late twentieth-century debates over the German catastrophe and the Holocaust. It may also reflect the desire of many historians to defend modernity from the postmodern critique, which seemed to threaten their hold on historical truth. Whatever the reason, historians have since 2000 been remarkably tenacious in their commitment to ‘modernity’. Among intellectual historians, those studying Enlightenment have made a point of defending their subject’s equivalence

24 Koselleck, ‘“Space of experience” and “horizon of expectation”: two historical categories’ (1976), Futures Past, 267–88.

25 Again, the balance between history and philosophy is debated by commentators. For Frank R., Ankersmit, ‘Koselleck on “Histories” versus “History”; or, historical ontology versus historical epistemology’, History and Theory, 60:4 (2021), 36–58, it is only as ontology that Koselleck’s philosophy transcends its Eurocentric historical premises.

26 Koselleck, ‘On the meaning and absurdity of history’ (1997), also ‘History, law and justice’ (1986), both in Sediments of Time, respectively 177–96, and 117–36, at 123–4. I am grateful to Clara Maier for explaining the context and significance of these essays to me.

27 Hence, presumably, Koselleck’s brusque description of Quentin Skinner as ‘a conventional historian concerned with a load of normative concepts’, quoted by Roberto Breña, ‘Tensions and challenges of intellectual history in contemporary Latin America’, Contributions to the History of Concepts, 16:1 (2021), 89–115, at 98–9.

to the cause of modernity.28 As we shall see, ‘global intellectual history’ has also given the concept a new lease of life, as modernity is projected as both the condition of dialogue and the focus of dispute between the West and the intellectual cultures of Asia.29 The continuing appeal of Koselleck’s thesis may owe more than it should to historians’ loyalty to a concept of modernity rather more positive than his own.

This point has not escaped critics. Among philosophers, one who engaged repeatedly and not unsympathetically with Koselleck’s theses was Paul Ricoeur. Ricoeur was nonetheless critical of the extent to which Koselleck had identified his concept of ‘History in the singular’ with modernity. ‘Modernity’, Ricoeur thought, had become a ‘conceptual epic’, culminating in the possessive ‘our modernity’, which was represented as a global phenomenon, and even as a tribunal. Rather than possessing a continuous existence, Ricoeur pointed out, modernity claims had taken different forms at different times, and could not be linked to a single conception of history or of temporality.30 For the medievalist and critical theorist Kathleen Davis, Koselleck’s account of the temporality of modernity was designed to rescue Carl Schmitt’s theory of secularisation at the expense of a middle ages supposedly trapped in theology.31 Among historians, Christopher Clark has sounded a note of caution, remarking on the way in which recent studies of temporality have ‘tended to be engineered from within by a more or less explicit theory of modernisation’, as if modernity itself was the driving force. Clark’s study of the ‘chronopolitics’ of successive Prussian and German regimes shows instead that modernisation took different forms under the different regimes, which had very different understandings of their relation to history and its temporalities.32

It is the extent to which Koselleck’s theses concerning temporality were tied to a strong modernity theory which should give pause to historians of political thought. The intuition that the political upheavals of the later eighteenth century were articulated in a new concept of revolution, one characterised by a sense that the time of politics could suddenly accelerate, was a historical insight of unusual originality, with far-reaching implications.33 But inserted into a pre-determined account of modernity, it became hostage to large-scale propositions about temporality and

28 John Robertson, ‘Enlightenment and modernity, historians and philosophers’, International Journal for History, Culture and Modernity, 8:3–4 (2020), 278–321.

29 Despite the misgivings of Dipesh Chakrabarty, ‘The muddle of modernity’, misgivings shared by the other (but not all) participants in the roundtable ‘Historians and the question of “modernity”’, American Historical Review, 116:3 (2011), 663–75, within 631–751.

30 Paul Ricoeur, Memory, History, Forgetting, translated by Kathleen Blamey and David Pellauer, (Chicago and London, 2004), 296–314. Ricoeur had previously engaged with Koselleck in Time and Narrative, 3 vols. (1984–1988).

31 Kathleen Davis, Periodization and Sovereignty. How ideas of Feudalism and Secularization govern the Politics of Time (Philadelphia, 2008), 77–95.

32 Clark, Time and Power, ‘Conclusion and epilogue’, 211–26, quotation from 213.

33 For an example of whose development, see Mackinnon, ‘The Right to Rebel’, later in this volume, Chapter 13.

historicity which narrowed rather than enlarged the scope for further enquiry. As I shall now argue, another approach to the history of political thought may offer a better way into the relation between time, history, and political thinking, yielding richer, more varied, accounts of their interaction. There is no need for the history of political thought to be pulled into the conceptual black hole of ‘modernity’.

3

It is the case that other historians of political thought have made their own claims on the ‘modern’. These claims have tended to be associated with the period before rather than after 1800. Once John Dunn had demonstrated the strength of Locke’s Christianity, thereby disqualifying him from being the first ‘modern’, secular and liberal political philosopher, the way was open for Hobbes to take up the role.34 That Hobbes was qualified to do so was suggested by Quentin Skinner in The Foundations of Modern Political Thought (1978), at the end of which he credited Hobbes with completing the foundations of the modern theory of the state.35 Thirty years later, and with a different methodological framing, Skinner extended the story to the present, arguing in ‘A genealogy of the modern state’ that of several competing possibilities, a version of the Hobbesian concept of the state was still the one to be preferred.36 But while Skinner was expressing a normative preference,37 he was not laying claim to modernity itself. He could hardly do so, since he was simultaneously recovering and advocating an avowedly ancient, ‘Roman’ concept of personal and political liberty.38 Closer to doing so, perhaps, was Richard Tuck’s alternative claim that Grotius inaugurated the ‘modern’ theory of natural law.39 The suggestion effectively equated modern with Protestant, in line with the Weberian association of Protestantism with aspects of modernity. But the implied segregation of the natural law of the Catholic Second Scholastic as, at best, pre-modern does not stand up to scrutiny: Grotius was the Scholastics’ closest interlocutor.40

34 John Dunn, The Political Thought of John Locke. An Historical Account of the Argument of the ‘Two Treatises of Government’ (Cambridge, 1969).

35 Quentin Skinner, The Foundations of Modern Political Thought, 2 vols. (Cambridge, 1978); on Hobbes, II, 349–58: ‘Conclusion’. Qualifying reflections in Brett, ‘Between history, politics and law’, 43–4.

36 Quentin Skinner, ‘A genealogy of the modern state’, Proceedings of the British Academy, 162 (2009), 325–70.

37 Melissa Lane, ‘Doing our own thinking for ourselves: on Quentin Skinner’s genealogical turn’, Journal of the History of Ideas, 73:1 (2012), 71–82.

38 Quentin Skinner, Liberty before Liberalism (Cambridge, 1998); and now, ‘On neo-Roman liberty: a response and reassessment’, in Hannah Dawson and Annelien de Dijn, eds., Rethinking Liberty before Liberalism (Cambridge, 2022), 233–66.

39 Richard Tuck, ‘The “modern” theory of natural law’, in Anthony Pagden, ed., The Languages of Political Theory in early modern Europe (Cambridge, 1987), 99–119.

40 Annabel S. Brett, Changes of State. Nature and the Limits of the City in early modern Natural Law (Princeton and Oxford, 2011); Sarah Mortimer, Reformation, Resistance, and Reason of State 1517–1625 (Oxford, 2021).

In any case, as another historian of political thought, John Pocock, has pointed out, the ‘modern’ is a term with its own history. In the first instance, it was used of all history that was not ‘ancient’: on this understanding, modern history began in the late third century, and included almost the entire history of the Christian Church. Around 1500, there developed a sharper differentiation, related to the three inventions supposed to be unknown in antiquity, printing, gunpowder and the compass. In the late seventeenth century, the Querelle of the ‘Ancients and Moderns’ enlarged the field of possible differences to cover the arts and sciences, population, and forms of government; by the mid-eighteenth century, commerce had been added to the list.41 By 1800, therefore, the term ‘modern’ had a recognised application, reasons had been advanced to prefer the modern world to the ancient, and the adjective had begun to add some value to what it qualified. But it was not a thing, with an independent existence. It was a construction of the thinkers who adopted the term. If the history of political thought is to extend to the concept of ‘modernity’, it can only be on this basis. As we shall now see, it was on the same basis that Pocock set out to explore the roles that time and history have played in political thought.

In a pair of articles published in 1962, Pocock set out an approach to the history of political thought which not only drew inspiration from the same ‘linguistic turn’ that informed the work of Skinner and Dunn, but also opened up the relation between political and historical thinking.42 As is well known, the focus of this approach is on the languages in which politics have been conceptualised, articulated, argued over and acted out. The approach is indebted to Wittgenstein’s philosophy of language in two respects particularly relevant to discussion of time and history in political thought: in its recognition of the plurality of language, and in its conviction that languages forming a more or less coherent field of discourse will set their own criteria of validation.

Plurality allows for overlap between languages, but denies that there must be a common denominator across them. What counts as political is therefore not a pregiven: political thought extends across languages which capture multiple forms of human association from different angles, and does not always reduce to ‘the state’. It is for the historian to identify which languages they choose to study, and which are in play in any selection of texts; if the authored text remains the focus of enquiry, what texts and their authors are doing is established by setting them in the context of the languages at work within them, and the institutional, social and immediately political settings (courts, law-courts, churches, universities, bureaucracies, parliaments, forms of publication) in which the languages have developed. The relevant

41 John G. A. Pocock, ‘Perceptions of modernity in early modern historical thinking’, Intellectual History Review, 17:1 (2007), 55–63.

42 John G. A. Pocock, ‘The history of political thought: a methodological enquiry’, and ‘The origins of study of the past: a comparative approach’, reprinted unrevised from articles originally published in 1962 in John G. A. Pocock, Political Thought and History. Essays on Theory and Method (Cambridge, 2009), 3–19, 145–86.

Turn static files into dynamic content formats.

Create a flipbook
Issuu converts static files into: digital portfolios, online yearbooks, online catalogs, digital photo albums and more. Sign up and create your flipbook.