The matter of empire: metaphysics and mining in colonial peru orlando bentancor - The full ebook ver

Page 1


Visit to download the full and correct content document: https://textbookfull.com/product/the-matter-of-empire-metaphysics-and-mining-in-colo nial-peru-orlando-bentancor/

More products digital (pdf, epub, mobi) instant download maybe you interests ...

Private Politics and Peasant Mobilization: Mining in Peru 1st Edition Maria-Therese Gustafsson (Auth.)

https://textbookfull.com/product/private-politics-and-peasantmobilization-mining-in-peru-1st-edition-maria-therese-gustafssonauth/

Indian Migration and Empire A Colonial Genealogy of the Modern State 1st Edition Radhika Mongia

https://textbookfull.com/product/indian-migration-and-empire-acolonial-genealogy-of-the-modern-state-1st-edition-radhikamongia/

Colonial Literature and the Native Author: Indigeneity and Empire 1st Edition Jane Stafford (Auth.)

https://textbookfull.com/product/colonial-literature-and-thenative-author-indigeneity-and-empire-1st-edition-jane-staffordauth/

Scottish Presbyterianism and Settler Colonial Politics: Empire of Dissent 1st Edition Valerie Wallace (Auth.)

https://textbookfull.com/product/scottish-presbyterianism-andsettler-colonial-politics-empire-of-dissent-1st-edition-valeriewallace-auth/

Colonial Trauma A Study of the Psychic and Political Consequences of Colonial Oppression in Algeria Karima Lazali

https://textbookfull.com/product/colonial-trauma-a-study-of-thepsychic-and-political-consequences-of-colonial-oppression-inalgeria-karima-lazali/

Seeds of Control Japan s Empire of Forestry in Colonial Korea Weyerhaeuser Environmental Books 1st Edition

David Fedman Paul S Sutter

https://textbookfull.com/product/seeds-of-control-japan-s-empireof-forestry-in-colonial-korea-weyerhaeuser-environmentalbooks-1st-edition-david-fedman-paul-s-sutter/

The Metaphysics of Truth Douglas Edwards

https://textbookfull.com/product/the-metaphysics-of-truthdouglas-edwards/

The Primacy of Metaphysics Christopher Peacocke

https://textbookfull.com/product/the-primacy-of-metaphysicschristopher-peacocke/

Ontology and the ambitions of metaphysics 1st Edition

Hofweber

https://textbookfull.com/product/ontology-and-the-ambitions-ofmetaphysics-1st-edition-hofweber/

THE MATTER OF EMPIRE

ILLUMINATIONS:

CULTURAL FORMATIONS OF THE AMERICAS SERIES

METAPHYSICS AND

THE MATTER OF EMPIRE

MINING IN

COLONIAL PERU

ORLANDO BENTANCOR

UNIVERSITY OF PITTSBURGH PRESS

Published by the University of Pittsburgh Press, Pittsburgh, Pa., 15260

Copyright © 2017, University of Pittsburgh Press

All rights reserved

Manufactured in the United States of America

Printed on acid-free paper 10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1

Cataloging-in-Publication data is available from the Library of Congress

ISBN 13: 978-0-8229-4460-7

ISBN 10: 0-8229-4460-X

Cover design by Joel W. Coggins

To Verónica

CONTENTS

Acknowledgments ix

Introduction: Imperium, Metaphysical Instrumentalism, and Potosí Mining 1

1. Grounding the Empire: Francisco de Vitoria’s Political Physics 40

2. The Impasses of Instrumentalism: Revisiting the Polemics between Sepúlveda and Las Casas 95

3. Mastering Nature: José de Acosta’s Pragmatic Instrumentalism 151

4. From Imperial Reason to Instrumental Reason: The Ideology of the Circle of Toledo 217

5. The Exhaustion of Natural Subordination: Solórzano Pereira and the Demise of Metaphysical Instrumentalism 284

Notes 353 Bibliography 377 Index 389

ACKNOWLEDGMENTS

This project would have been impossible without the generous guidance and tutelage of Cristina Moreiras, Gustavo Verdesio, and Gareth Williams, my professors at the University of Michigan. Seminars taught by Jossiana Arroyo, Catherine Brown, Santiago Colás, and Javier Sanjinés informed my thinking and research. This study benefited from conversations with my former classmates Luis Martin Cabrera, Manuel Chinchilla, Andrea Fanta, Patty Keller, Andrea Marinescu, Jon Snyder, Fernando Velasquez, and Marcelino Viera.

I also want to thank Susana Draper for her profound and honest observations. Anna More helped to shape my thinking through innumerable hours of intellectual exchange and generous discussions. My thanks go also to Ivonne del Valle for her feedback and constant support.

My gratitude goes to my former colleagues at the University of Southern California: Daniela Bleichmar, Roberto Ignacio Díaz, Gabriel Giorgi, Peggy Kamuf, Karen Pinkus, and Sherry Velasco. It is not possible to do justice to the many different forms in which my colleagues at Barnard College have supported this book. Thanks go to Ronald Briggs, Maja Horn, Alfred MacAdam, and Wadda Rios-Font. My colleagues at Columbia—Carlos Alonso, Patricia Grieve, Seth Kimmel, Alberto Medina, Graciela Montaldo, Alessandra Russo, Jesús R. Velasco—fostered an en-

vironment both diverse and challenging. I want to thank Seth Kimmel for the title of this book.

The project was also shaped by dialogues with Santa Arias, Ralph Bauer, John Beverley, Sara Castro-Klarén, Sibylle Fischer, Ross Hamilton, Stella Nair, Ricardo Padrón, Mary Louise Pratt, Jose Rabasa, Benita Sampedro, Freya Schiwy, Patricia Seed, Elvira Vilches, Lisa Voigt, and Nicolás Wey-Gómez. I want to thank Bram Acosta, Jon Beasley-Murray, Oscar Cabezas, Patrick Dove, Alessandro Fornazzari, Erin Graft, John Kraniauskas, Brett Levinson, Alberto Moreiras, Samuel Steinberg, and Sergio Villalobos for conference panels and conversations that have enriched my ideas. I am grateful to the class discussions I had with Santiago Acosta, Anayvelyse Allen-Mossman, Miguel Ibañez Aristondo, Jae Young Chang, Omar Durán-García, Analía Lavin, Alexandra Mendez, Cybele Pena, and Roberto Valdovinos. My special thanks go to Noel Blanco Mourelle for his patience and friendship.

Andrew Ascherl, Brian Green, and Alfred MacAdam helped me with the translation of the primary sources quoted in this book. Elizabeth Castelli encouraged me to apply for a grant from Barnard College that permitted me to revise the manuscript. I am indebted to Andrew Ascherl’s help in the preparation of the manuscript and to his sharp theoretical insights. At Pittsburgh University Press, I want to thank John Beverley and Sara Castro-Klarén, the series editors, as well as Josh Shanholtzer and the two anonymous readers.

I would like to thank my parents for encouraging me to pursue my intellectual goals. And above all, I thank my wife, Verónica Laguna, for her infinite and unconditional love.

THE MATTER OF EMPIRE

INTRODUCTION

IMPERIUM , METAPHYSICAL

INSTRUMENTALISM, AND

POTOSÍ

MINING

THE METAPHYSICAL FOUNDATIONS OF IMPERIAL INSTRUMENTAL REASON

Discovered in 1545, the Cerro Rico (Rich Hill) of Potosí immediately became the main source of silver for the Spanish Empire, fueling both its political project of a Christian monarchy and the first global economy.1 Even as they transformed Peruvian metals into the money that kept the empire together, sixteenth-century Spaniards also understood mining through long-standing metaphysical beliefs concerning the essence of matter. This metaphysical framework assumed that the natural world was composed of a raw and defective material that had to be dominated from above and directed to a higher end. Surprisingly, this metaphysics also framed the writings on natural law that were central to Spain’s justification of its empire. An examination of the interactions between early political writings and writings on mining will show that the particular confluence of Iberian imperial practices and philosophical ideas in the Americas frames technological and capitalist modernity as both an imperial and a metaphysical project.

I make this argument through a contrapuntal reading of the sixteenth-century debates on Spanish sovereignty in the Americas and treatises on natural history and mining written between 1520 and 1640. Whether political or natural-historical, these texts all invoke an ontological frame derived from a “natural order” to justify (and occasionally to

question) material practices such as compulsory labor in the colonial Andes (mita) and refining techniques for the amalgamation of metals (beneficio). We trace the development of this ontological frame over the course of a century and a half, beginning with the early attempts to justify the conquest and compulsory labor in the mines and ending with texts on mining written as the Spanish Empire entered its terminal decline.

The texts along this trajectory often fall into the inherent paradox of metaphysical instrumentalism: conceiving nature as open to technical manipulation resulted in the entanglement of ends and means. For instance, Spaniards consistently justified the extraction of silver and the production of money by conceiving artificial mastery (or means) as determined by a natural teleology (or end). The metaphysical problem encountered in this collapse of ends and means was that the crass and profane material means were continually threatened with the danger of becoming an autonomous end in itself, undermining the superior ends they were supposed to obey. Thus, refining techniques and compulsory labor cost the Crown the lives of the Indian vassals, while the production and circulation of silver enriched a vast credit network that benefited competing European powers, in each case avoiding the ideal imperial end. While Spanish ideology sought to create a closed metaphysical circle that dedicated all practices to a united end, however, writers were well aware of the open-ended nature of both mining production and the global economy. As the Spanish Empire entered into decline in the seventeenth century, this dependence on material means proved ultimately incompatible with perfect ends and produced clear and endemic ideological inconsistencies.

Spanish imperial science and mining are traditionally studied separately from Spanish political theory, but here these two discourses are seen as isomorphic, interpenetrating one another at every level. By foregrounding the common Scholastic basis and the interaction between these two bodies of literature, moreover, this discussion contributes to a general reevaluation of the Scholastic roots of modernity in the fields of philosophy and the history of science. A systematic examination of metaphysical language employed in distinct disciplines allows us to narrate how the view of both nature and humans as malleable material is the result of the instrumentalist presuppositions inherent in imperial ideology. Against the assumption that scientific modernity began with the Protestant empiricists, I argue that this Western metaphysical instrumen-

talism is the origin of the contemporary reduction of nature to technologically disposable material.2 This metaphysical ideology developed in the context of colonial Andean mining, and there was a specifically colonial indigenous attribution of life to the mineral world that was not exterior to but, rather, dialectically engaged with imperial metaphysics. This engagement still provides modern scholars with the basis for a critique of imperial metaphysical instrumentalism.

SCHOLASTICISM AND IBERIAN IMPERIAL IDEOLOGY

In order to examine the common Scholastic basis of imperial politics and mining, we must begin with attempts to ground the Spanish Empire in Aquinas’s metaphysics. After the discovery and conquest the Spaniards tried to justify the appropriation of riches and the practice of mining in the New World. Scholasticism provided the theological and philosophical foundations for justifying the whole colonial enterprise.3 The name of the movement that engaged in thinking contemporary politics through the work of Aquinas is the School of Salamanca.4

The founder of the School of Salamanca was the Dominican Francisco de Vitoria (1492–1546). Domingo de Soto (1494–1560), Melchor Cano (1509–1560), and Francisco Suárez (1548–1617) were also part of this movement.5 The fundamental sources for Spanish Scholastics were Aristotle, Thomas Aquinas, Roman jurisprudence, civil and ecclesiastical law, and the Decretales, a collection assembled in the eighth century under the auspices of Pope Gregorio IX. Spanish Scholastics continued the tradition initiated by Cayetano (also known as Tomás Vio) of commenting on entire sections of Thomas Aquinas’s Summa Theologica. The AristotelianThomist tradition provided ways of confronting the threats presented by the via moderna and crystallized in Lutheranism, Machiavellianism, Erasmus’s pacifism, and Ockham’s nominalism.6 Aquinas’s “rationalism” was a perfect antidote to both Luther’s theological voluntarism and Machiavelli’s reason of state. The School of Salamanca opposed the pacifism of Juan Luis Vives, who saw in Charles V the triumphant unification dreamed of by Dante and Erasmus but condemned both Scholasticism and Spain’s militarism by appealing to Augustine’s City of God.

Francisco de Vitoria followed the model of the University of Paris that replaced nominalism with Thomism. Aquinas’s philosophy was not only a christianization of Aristotle but also a synthesis of Aristotelianism and

Platonism. Aquinas metaphysics subsumed the theology of Augustine, Roman Law, and Cicero’s natural right under a new paradigm. This paradigm accommodated empirical and factual knowledge of the world with the ontological realism of universal forms. Since Thomism defends the capacity to understand reality through the grasping of its essence, it proved useful for assigning sense to empirical facts. Aquinas’s metaphysics and politics was a synthesis of Platonic doctrine of participation with Aristotelian causation.7 The ultimate principles of Thomist ontology and theology were employed to assign sense and finality to a union of the factual (temporal) and the transcendent (eternal) realms in order to justify the evangelization and conquest of the New World. It provided a strong accountability to existing laws by grounding them in “rational” and “natural” finality. Therefore, Aquinas’s providentialism provided a strong sense of legitimacy to the prince’s authority by appealing to self-evident and ultimate principles capable of grounding the imperium as capacity to command. The political and epistemological power of Scholasticism depended on what can be summarized in the principle of subordination of the part to the whole, imperfect matter to perfect form, and material means to an immaterial end.

The task undertaken by the Spaniards was to justify their sovereignty over the newly discovered peoples by invoking their imperfect nature. Their imperfect nature, crystallized in their lack of civilization, had to be directed to their proper end, which was the common good, civilization, and salvation. The same procedure was applied to nature, which was understood as temporal means that could be used by directing it to humans’ ends. Such a providentialist view of metals presupposed that available resources were a raw matter that could be employed to further Catholic expansion. This principle makes it possible to read both political writings and texts on mining through their common presuppositions, which is metaphysical instrumentalism—the ultimate ideology of the Spanish Empire.8 In order to explain the instrumentalist presuppositions behind Aquinas’s metaphysics, let us move now to the principle of the natural subordination of matter to form and means to an end.

PRINCIPLE AS ORIGIN OF DOMINATION

Let us start by explaining what a principle is. For Aristotle, and thus for Aquinas, a principle is a beginning or starting point that initiates the

existence or motion of something else (Metaphysics 5). For Aquinas, everything existing or moving owes its existence or movement to something else. For this reason, principles surpass moving or existing things in power. In Chapter 1, Book 5, Metaphysics 1012b34–1013a23, Aristotle explains the notion of principle as origin or inception by using different examples. In the first example, beginning means a part of a thing “from which one would start first, e.g. a line or a road has a beginning in either of the contrary distinctions” (Aristotle, Basic Works, 752). According to the second example, in “learning we must sometimes begin not from the first point and the beginning of the subject but from the point from which we should learn most easily” (752). In the third example, Aristotle refers to things that have their origin inside their nature, such as the heart of an animal, or “as the keel of a ship and the foundation of a house” (752). The fourth example is that of things that have their origin outside their nature, “as a child comes from its father and its mother” (752). The fifth example refers to the origin as the will that moves something else; it locates the best examples in “the magistracies in cities, and oligarchies and monarchies and tyrannies, [which] are called archai and so are the arts, and of these especially the architectonic arts” (752). In the sphere of knowledge, the origin is “that from which a thing can first be known—this is also called the beginning of the thing, e.g. the hypotheses are beginning of demonstrations” (752). What all these examples have in common is “to be the first point from which a thing either is or comes to be or is known” (752). In other words, a principle as origin is something that comes first and has certain preeminence because it is more important. Since a principle involves commanding and subordinating, it is useful to examine Aquinas’s commentary on the fifth example.

Before analyzing this example, however, it is instructive to say that Aquinas classifies these above-mentioned examples in two categories. According to the first sense, “a principle means that part of a thing which is first generated and from which the generation of the things begins” (Aquinas, Commentary on Aristotle’s Metaphysics, 278). The cases of the line, the road, and the foundation of the house belong to this first sense of principle. Yet there is a second sense in which “a principle means that from which a thing’s process of generation begins but which is outside the thing” (279). One example of the first would be that of the father as the origin of the child. Indeed, within this category of things that have their principle outside themselves, he finds “natural beings, in which

the principle of generation is said to be the first thing from which motion naturally begins in those things, which come about through motion” (279). The second case of things that have their origin outside themselves, which is also Aristotle’s fifth example, is that of “human acts, whether ethical or political, in which that by whose will or intention others are moved or changed is called a principle” (278–79). For Aquinas, both the example of the magistracies and civil power and the example of natural generation and corruptions, such as the father and the child, belong to the categories of external principles that cause the movement of something. Imperial power, which for Aquinas means sovereignty, implies this capacity to move its subjects, since “those who hold civil, imperial, or even tyrannical power in states are said to have the principal places” (279). By the will of the prince “all things came to pass or are put into motion in the states” (279). Those who have civil power “are put in command of particular offices in states as judges and persons of this kind” (279). For Aquinas, clearly, both the cases of natural movement and political subjection fall within the parameters of being moved by an external principle that precedes and exceeds the moved thing or subject. Civil power, the power of the state, is clearly an example of a principle that moves its subjects by subordinating them.

Finally, there is another example that falls under the fifth sense of principle in Aristotle and the category of external causation in Aquinas, which is the subordination of inferior arts to superior arts:

For the arts too in a similar way are called principles of artificial things, because the motion necessary for producing an artifact begins from art. And of these arts the architectonic, which “derive their name” from the word principle, i.e., those called principal arts, are said to be principles in the highest degree. For by architectonic arts we mean those which govern subordinate arts, as the art of navigator governs the art of ship-building, and the military art governs the art of horsemanship. (279)

The example of this kind of subordination is also an example of subordination based on an external principle. This example is so important that it also appears in Chapter 1, Book 1, Metaphysics 981a29–981b2, where Aristotle writes, “For men of experience know that the thing is so, but do not know why, while the others know the ‘why’ and the cause. Hence we

think also that the master-workers in each craft are more honorable and know in a truer sense and are wiser than the manual workers, because they know the causes of the things that are done” (Basic Works, 690). Aquinas comments on this passage, saying that “In order to understand this we must note that architect means chief artist, from techne, meaning chief, and archos, meaning art” (Aquinas, Commentary on Aristotle’s Metaphysics, 9). The superior art is the one that “performs a more important operation” (9). Moreover, Aquinas classifies the artist’s operations between disposing the material of the artifacts and directing them to an end:

Carpenters, for example, by cutting and planing the wood, dispose matter for the form of a ship. Another operation is directed to introducing this form into matter, for example when someone builds a ship out of wood which has been disposed and prepared. A third operation is directed to use of the finished product, and this is the highest operation. But the first operation is the lowest because it is directed to the second and second to the third. Hence the shipbuilder is a superior artist compared with the one who prepares the wood; and the navigator, who uses the completed ship, is a superior artist compared with the shipbuilder. (9–10)

Therefore, just like the natural hierarchies of the physical world and the human hierarchies of the political world, the hierarchy of the arts is an example of external subordination. The subordination of the material to the artist and then the subordination of this artist to a superior artist are based on the fact that the superior artist has a clear vision of the end of the final product. What all examples of principles share is being the first thing out of which things arise and are ruled. The principle precedes that of which it is a principle. It precedes everything else. It is presupposed. In the case of external causation, there is always an agent that is preeminent and superior and that commands what is subordinated and inferior. The very notion of principle and its ultimate metaphysical character is based on presupposing that the principle is both inception and source of domination. The principle commands, which means it subordinates and moves. A guiding hypothesis of the present book is that the commanding character of the principle is the result of the transposition of human technical manipulation to the realm of metaphysics. Another way of framing

this problem is, as will become evident in the following sections, that the intrinsic presupposition of this kind of movement is that of technical manipulation.

As explained above, natural, political, and technical subordinations are grounded on external principles. In Article 1, Summa Theologica IIaIIae, Aquinas joins the notion of natural order and that of political subordination by grounding both in higher principle:

In natural order, it happens of necessity that higher things move lower things by excellence of the natural power divinely given to them. Hence in human affairs also superior must move inferior by their will, by virtue of a divinely established authority. But to move by reason and by will is to command. And so just as in the divinely instituted natural order lower things are necessarily subject to higher things and are moved by them, so too in human affairs inferiors are bound to obey their superiors by virtue of the order of natural and Divine law. (Aquinas, Political Writings, 58)

The hierarchical division between higher (that is, moving and ruling) things and lower (or moved and inferior) things is part of a natural order. Natural subordination includes human affairs, which include politics, where rulers govern the ruled by commanding, or moving by reason and will. Both natural order and political subjection share in being part of providence, the divinely instituted natural order. In order to clarify the meaning of natural order or natural subordination, let us examine some key moments of Aquinas’s principles of nature, also known as the doctrine of hylomorphism. In Aquinas, there are three principles in nature: matter, form, and privation. While matter and form are principles in themselves (per se) because they are also positive causes, privation is an accidental principle (per accidends) because it cannot cause anything by itself. First, I will explain the notion of matter, since this principle also involves the principle of privation.

PRIME MATTER PRESUPPOSES INSTRUMENTAL MANIPULATION

The metaphysical status of the “prime matter” is that of a pure abstraction that separates all the sensual, empirical, and singular qualities of things by focusing on what they have in common. In his commentary to

Aristotle’s Physics, Aquinas defines “prime matter” as a lump of amorphous, plastic, raw material that has no consistency of its own since it exists only in a composite of matter. In Physics 191a7–15, Aristotle writes: “This underlying nature is an object of scientific knowledge, by analogy. For as the bronze is to the statue, the wood to the bed, or the matter and the formless before receiving form to any thing which has form, so is the underlying nature to substance, i.e., the ‘this’ or existent” (Basic Works, 232). Aquinas comments on this passage, saying that the abovementioned underlying nature, “which is first subject to mutation, i.e., primary matter, cannot be known in itself, since everything which is known is known only through form” (Commentary on Physics, 61). This means that if matter is the imperfect, passive potency that underlies all individual material entities, form is the idea, pattern, or blueprint that gives determination and consistency to these material entities.9 Matter is unknown and unintelligible, and only form is intelligible. This raw stuff present under every composite is pure passive potential to receive an exemplary pattern or “form” from above.10 Aquinas continues, explaining that “prime matter is, moreover, considered to be the subject of every form. But it is known by analogy, that is, according to proportion” (61). Since this amorphous material cannot be known, it can only be understood through the mediation of analogy. The analogy of proportion can be illustrated by saying that A stands in relation to B, as C stands in relation to D. Aquinas adds, “For we know that wood is other than the form of a bench and a bed, for sometimes it underlies to one form, at other times the other” (61). We know that matter is different from form because wood is different from the bed. Aquinas thinks that experience tells us that the same wood sometimes underlies one bed and sometimes another. From there, the intellect abstracts an underlying notion of matter common to the different forms. Aquinas continues, explaining that, “when, therefore, we see that air at times becomes water, it is necessary to say that there is something, which sometimes exists under the form of air, and that other times under the form of water” (61). For something to become something else there must be an underlying substrate to both entities. Moreover, “this something is other than the form of water and other than the form of air, as wood is something other than the form of a bench and other than the form of bed” (61). The basic reasoning is an analogy according to which prime matter is other than the form, just as wood is other than the bench. Aquinas ends the paragraph saying

“This ‘something,’ then, is related to these natural substances as bronze is related to the statue, and wood to the bed, and anything material and unformed to form. And this is called primary matter” (61).

This is the crucial moment that explains how metaphysical thinking knows that there is an amorphous passive potential matter common to all things. It is the result of an abstraction that separates matter from all its concrete qualifications by postulating it as something that underlies already formed things. But the question that arises is, How does the intellect arrive at this idea of prime matter as an imperfect and amorphous passive potency deprived of any concreteness? By analogy with human manipulation: the prime matter stands in relation to form in the same way that bronze stands in relation to the statue. Aristotelian-Thomist metaphysics arrives at the idea of an amorphous passive raw matter by way of an analogy with human manipulation. The principle of the natural subordination of matter to form results from the transposition of technical manipulation to the natural order. Matter is subordinated to form in the same way that the bronze is subordinated to form, which is the final product, the statue:

What is in potency cannot bring itself into a state of actuality. Bronze, for example, which is a statue in potency, does not make itself be a statue. It needs something actively working, which brings out the form of the statue from potency into act; I am speaking of the form of the generated thing, the form which we have said is the end-point of generation. . . . It is necessary, therefore that there be in addition to the matter and the form some principle which does something; and this is said to be what makes, or moves, or acts, or that from which the motion begins. (Bobik, 34–35)

Matter cannot produce anything because matter cannot bring itself into an actual object. It remains potential in the same way that bronze remains potential until the agent actualizes it by imposing a form on it. But form is the end-point of generation, or as Aquinas also says: “for form is the end of matter; therefore for matter to seek form is nothing other than matter being ordered to form as potency to act” (Commentary on Physics, 72). This means that the material means is subordinated to the form which is also the final cause. Therefore, Aquinas ties everything by saying that to matter, form, and privation there must be added an agent, which is the principle or “that from which the motion begins.”

In Chapter 4e, Book 8, Physics 256a21–256b3, Aristotle sustains that, since every movement requires a mover, there must be a prime mover that moves itself in order to avoid an infinite regress. He exemplifies this argument by appealing to technical motion or instrumental manipulation:

Every movement moves something and moves it with something, either with himself or with something else: e.g., a man moves a thing either himself or with a stick and a thing is knocked down either by the wind itself or by a stone propelled by the wind. But it is impossible for that with which a thing is moved to move it without being moved by that which imparts motion by its own agency: on the other hand, if a thing imparts its motion by its own agency, it is not necessary that there should be anything else with which it imparts motion, whereas if there is a different thing with which it imparts motion, there must be something that imparts motion not with something else, but with itself, or else there will be an infinite series. If, then, anything is a movement while being itself moved, the series must stop somewhere and not be infinite. Thus, if the stick moves something in virtue of being moved by hand, the hand moves the stick: and if something else moves with the hand, the hand also is moved by something different from itself. So when motion by means of an instrument is at each state caused by something different from the instrument, this must always be preceded by something else which imparts motion with itself. Therefore, if this last movement is in motion and there is nothing else that moves it, it must move itself. So this reasoning also shows that, when a thing is moved, if it is not moved by something that moves itself, the series brings us at some time or other to a movement of this kind. (Basic Works, 367–68)

Since everything that moves must be moved either by itself or by another agent, there must also be an agent that moves itself. This will become an important argument for proving the existence of God, the Prime Mover, a principle of all movements. Aquinas comments this passage by saying that “every mover moves something and moves by something, either by itself or by another lower mover” (Commentary on Physics, 551). For example, “a man moves a stone either by himself or by a stick, and the wind hurls something to the ground either by its own power or by a stone which it moves” (551). Aquinas continues, explaining that “it is impossible for that which moves as an instrument to move something

without a principal mover” (551). In other words, instruments do not move themselves. Aquinas goes on: “For example, a stick cannot move without a hand.” Moreover, “no one would doubt that the second mover is the instrument of the first” (551). The consequence of the incapacity of an instrument to move itself is none other than the existence of a thing that moves itself: “Just as he said above that if something is moved by another there must be something which is not moved, but not vice versa, so here he says by descending that if there is an instrument by which a mover moves there must be something which moves, not by an instrument, but by itself, or else there is an infinite series of instruments. This is the same as an infinite series of movers, which is impossible, as was shown above” (551). If there are instruments, things that are moved by human hands, then there must be a first mover since it is impossible to have a series of infinite instruments. The machine of the world requires a first mover, an external, transcendent cause that moves everything else. There is a gradation of power and capacity to move that goes from God, which is absolutely perfect (self-subsistent, self-moving) to nonliving things, which are imperfect (dependent and moved by another). In the middle there are corporeal things that are composites of matter and forms. The world is a hierarchical, natural order where matter is subjected to different forms that are intellectual, sensitive, and vegetative. While God is the ultimate agent who moves instruments, matter is the lowest imperfect principle, which is itself an instrument of the form, whether it is an intellectual, vegetative, or sensitive soul: “the whole of corporeal nature is an underlying subject to the soul, and it is related to it as matter and instrument” (Bobik, 141). In sum, the principle of the natural subordination of imperfect matter to perfect form is inseparable from an instrumental understanding of nature. To recapitulate, the three examples of principles, as such, are natural, political, and technical subordination. The three aspects are joined into one principle, which is exemplified with the example of the bronze statue.

The example of bronze provided by Aquinas and Aristotle illustrating both natural subordination and political subjection is an example borrowed from the arts. In this example, an artist (efficient cause) imposes a preexisting idea (perfect form, universal pattern, blueprint, or soul) over a prime matter (pure passive instrumental potency) in order to produce a statue (the final product). Aquinas employs the metaphor of the craftsman or the architect who imposes a preexisting rational order (forms,

ideas, universal patterns, exempla) over an amorphous, chaotic, imperfect, and incomplete matter in order to achieve a perfect, complete, and self-sufficient product. Let us return to the domain of political subjection, or empire as subjection, in order to see how Aquinas joins the natural order with the compulsory character of the law. In Article 1, Summa Theologica IaIIae.93, titled “Whether the eternal law is supreme reason existing in God,” we read:

Just as in every craftsman there preexists a rational pattern of the things, which are to be made by his art, so too in every governor there must preexist a rational pattern of the order of the things, which are to be done by those subject to his government. And just as the rational pattern of the thing to be made by art is called art, or the exemplar of the products of that art, so too the rational pattern existing in him who governs the acts of his subjects bears the character of the law, provided that the other conditions which we have mentioned above are also present. Now God is the Creator of all things by His Wisdom, and He stands in the same relation to them as a craftsman does to the products of his art, as noted in the First Part. But he is also the governor of all the acts and motions that are to be found in each single creature, as was also noted in the First Part. Hence just as the rational pattern of the Divine wisdom has the character of law in relation to all the things which are moved by it to their proper end. (Political Writings, 102; my emphasis)

The relation of proportion here is the same as the one explained above between the bronze and the statue, where prime matter stands in relation to the final form in the same way that bronze stands in relation to a statue. Now both God and the monarch stand in relation to the subject in the same way that the artist stands in relation to the amorphous matter. These efficient causes have a preexisting end in mind that functions as a rational pattern, blueprint, or prototype. This preexisting idea lives in the mind of the Divine Artifice who then proceeds to tame the amorphous material in order to obtain a final product. In the example provided by Aquinas, the formal cause of the product of art is the preexisting idea. The efficient cause is the Divine Artifice itself. The material cause is the amorphous and plastic material, a passive potency that receives the form in the mind of the Divine Artifice. Finally, the final cause is the product of art itself. The principle of

natural subordination implies that there is a superior power that moves things to their proper end. There is a tautological performativity at work in the capacity of the principle to command amorphous matter. This tautological character resides in the fact that ends are mandatory because they have been imposed by the principle. In order to go beyond the mere tautological relation between origin and end, and to prove that the command is not just arbitrary but both rational and natural, Aquinas, following Aristotle and Plato, has to appeal to the metaphor of the artisan. Examples similar to that of the statue appear in De regimine principum where Aquinas states:

That it is necessary for men who live together to be subject to a diligent rule by someone. To fulfill this intention, we must begin by explaining how the title king is to be understood. Now in all cases where things are directed towards some end but it is possible to proceed in more than one way, it is necessary for there to be some guiding principle, so that the due end may be properly achieved. For example, a ship is driven in different directions according to the force of different winds, and it will not reach its final destination except by the industry of the steersman who guides it into port. . . . Man therefore needs something to guide him towards his end. (Political Writings, 5)

Here, in order to explain how guiding principles must direct things to an end and how the prince must direct men to their proper end, Aquinas employs the example of how the steersman guides the ship to its proper destination. In this example, just as in the example of the artist who makes a statue, there is a clear transposition of technique to the natural order and to politics.

As a result from the use of this example borrowed from technical mastery, there is an instrumentalist presupposition in Aquinas’s principle of the natural subordination of imperfect matter to the perfect end. Natural causation is preconceived as artificial causation.11 Natural mastery, the capacity of the principle to command, is like artificial mastery, the capacity of the artist to impose form over matter, directing it to the end.12 The reason behind this transposition of technique to nature is that principles cannot be demonstrated, because they are the origin of the demonstration. Although principles are absolutely necessary and, therefore, presupposed, they are impossible to know or demonstrate, since

they are themselves the origin of demonstration. Therefore, they can only be illustrated by using an imperfect analogy. The principle’s power to command—imperium itself—is illustrated by appealing to an example that backs up the principle itself. Within the frame of Scholastic metaphysics, the rational power to command is paradoxically understood as the capacity of human beings to mold an available raw material with human hands.

Therefore, Aquinas transfers the characteristics of instrumental manipulation to the natural world and political world. Despite appealing to instrumental manipulation in order to ground the capacity to command, Aquinas’s Aristotelian philosophy relegates instrumental manipulation to the status of a mere passive, inert human extension. Scholasticism disavows its own transposition of artificial mastery to natural causality by reducing technique to a mere medium—a neutral, instrumental device that requires an efficient cause to be set in motion and directed to a preexisting end—since artifacts “have no inner impulse to change” (Aristotle, Basic Writings, 236). The principle of the natural subordination of imperfect matter to perfect form presupposes metaphysical instrumentalism. Instrumentalism is metaphysical because it supposes the preexistence of a supersensory idea independent of the material world already inscribed in the commanding origin. Metaphysics is instrumentalist because it borrows its apparently self-evident character from examples borrowed from instrumental manipulation, such as statue making, ship navigation, or bridle making. Since metaphysics wants to preserve its necessary and, above all, natural character, it subordinates technique to a preexisting master by relegating the instrument to the status of a passive medium. Metaphysical instrumentalism conceives nature and politics as a means to an end because it masters technique by presupposing a master that controls technique itself. Matter is a manipulatable stock, an available material instrument ready to be directed to a higher end.

MODERNITY AS TECHNOLOGICAL DOMINATION IN HEIDEGGER

The instrumentalist presuppositions of metaphysics were the object of Martin Heidegger’s deconstruction of the history of Western philosophy. He is without a doubt the most influential philosopher of technology of the twentieth century.13 Such an uncontested influence is partially

based on Heidegger’s insight into the mutual co-constitution between metaphysical totalizations and global technological expansion. Moreover, for Heidegger, technological domination is part of self-revelation of being itself. As Arthur Bradley explains, for Heidegger “the history of the philosophy of technology from Aristotle to the epoch of contemporary techno-science effectively becomes the history of Being’s own self-disclosure—a disclosure that changes radically over time—to that being who is most equipped to receive it: Dasein” (68). The history of Western metaphysics is the attempt to legitimize technological domination of nature and human beings by endowing ultimate representations of being with a commanding power.14 These measuring principles have a history—a rise, a productive life, and a fall. Principles are not scientific since their role is to ground science. As Reiner Schürmann explains, for Heidegger the history of Western metaphysics is the history of the rise and fall of these principles, which are representations of an ontological origin that precedes and empowers being itself. In Heidegger’s words, “Metaphysics is history’s open space wherein it becomes a destining that the supersensory world, the ideas, God, the moral law, the authority of reason, progress, the happiness of the greatest number, culture, civilization, suffer the loss of their constructive force and become void” (“The World of Nietzsche,” in The Question Concerning Technology, 65). Each of these epochal principles is a failed attempt to provide a ground with normative force that would legitimate technological will to power. As Schürmann maintains, Heidegger’s history of Western metaphysics is structured around a central insight, which is that philosophy has been hypnotized by Aristotle’s teleology from beginning to end. As a matter of fact, Heidegger decreed that “This book [Aristotle’s Physics] determines the warp and woof of the whole of Western thinking, even at that place where it, as modern thinking, appears to think at odds with ancient thinking. But opposition is invariably comprised of a decisive, and often even perilous, dependence” (Heidegger, The Principle of Reason, 63). In Schürmann’s interpretation of Heidegger, Western metaphysics has been held captive by a teleocratic design, invented by Aristotle, that reaches its point of exhaustion with Nietzsche’s doctrine of the will to power: “Both Metaphysics and logic derive from the astonishment before what our hands can make out of some material” (On Being and Acting, 99). Schürmann contends that, for Heidegger, the Aristotelian concepts of origin and end do not result from speculation or syllogistic logic, “from the analysis of

Another random document with no related content on Scribd:

hurting ourselves like this? What is the good of it? Supposing—I only say supposing—supposing we let go, let the elastic slacken, followed our heart's desire, what then? Who would suffer? Helen, I suppose. Poor Helen!—I mustn't let her suffer like that, must I?

"It wasn't real love that I ever had for her; it was just mere physical infatuation. And now that's gone, all that's left is just dreadful pity—oh, pity that will not let me go! And yet what good is pity—the sort of pity that I have for her?

"Ever since I first knew you, you have been creeping into my heart ever so slowly and steadily, and I, because I never guessed what was happening, have yielded myself to you utterly. In fact, I am a man possessed by a devil—a good little devil—yet—"

He looked round and saw Helen standing by the side of him. He had not heard her approach. She might have been there some while, he reflected. Had she been looking over his shoulder? Did she know to whom was the letter he was writing?

He started, and instinctively covered as much of the writing as he could with the sleeve of his jacket.

"I didn't know you still wrote to Clare," she said, quietly.

"Who said I did?" he parried, with instant truculence.

"You're writing to her now."

"How do you know?"

"Never mind how I know. Answer me: you are, aren't you?"

"I refuse to answer such a question. Surely I haven't to tell you of every letter I write. If you've been spying over my shoulder it's your own fault. How would you like me to read all the letters you write?"

"I wouldn't mind in the least, Kenneth, if I thought you didn't trust me."

"Well, I do trust you, you see, and even if I didn't I shouldn't attempt such an unheard—of liberty. And if you can't trust me without censoring my correspondence, I'm afraid you'll have to go on mistrusting me."

"I don't want to censor your correspondence. I only want you to answer me a straight question: is that a letter to Clare that you're writing?"

"It's a most improper question, and I refuse to answer it."

"Very well.... I think it's time for dinner; hadn't you better finish the letter afterwards? Unless of course, it's very important."

During dinner she said: "I don't feel like staying in from now until bedtime. You'll want to finish your letter, of course, so I think, if you don't mind, I'll go to the local kinema."

"You can't go alone, can you?"

"There's nobody can very easily stop me, is there? You don't want to come with me, I suppose?"

"I'm afraid I don't care for kinemas much? Isn't there a theatre somewhere?"

"No. Only a kinema. I looked in the Seacliffe Gazette. In the summer there are Pierrots on the sands, of course."

"So you want to go alone to the kinema?"

"Yes."

"All right. But I'll meet you when it's over. Half-past ten, I suppose?"

"Probably about then. You don't mind me leaving you for a few hours, do you?"

"Oh, not at all. I hope you have a good time. I'm sure I can quite understand you being bored with Seacliffe. It's the deadest hole I've ever struck."

"But it's doing you good, isn't it?"

"Oh, yes, I daresay it is in that way."

She added, after a pause: "When you get back to the lounge you'll wonder where you put your half-written letter."

"What do you mean?" He suddenly felt in his inside coat-pocket. "Why—where is it? I thought I put it in my pocket. Who's got it? Have you?"

"Yes. You thought you put it in your pocket, I know But you didn't. You left it on the writing table and I picked it up when you weren't looking."

"Then you have got it?"

"Yes, I have got it."

He went red with rage. "Helen, I don't want to make a scene in front of the servants, but I insist on you giving up to me that letter. You've absolutely no right to it, and I demand that you give it me immediately."

"You shall have it after I've read it."

"Good God, Helen, don't play the fool with me! I want it now, this minute! Understand, I mean it! I want it now!"

"And I shan't give it to you."

He suddenly looked round the room. There was nobody there; the waitress was away; the two of them were quite alone. He rose out of his chair and with a second cautious glance round him went over to her and seized her by the neck with one hand while with the other he felt in her corsage for the letter. He knew that was where she would have put it. The very surprise of his movement made it successful. In another moment he had the letter in his hand. He stood above her, grim and angry, flaunting the letter high above her head. She made an upward spring for his hand, and he, startled by her quick retaliation, crumpled the letter into a heap and flung it into the fire at the side of the room. Then they both stared at each other in silence.

"So it's come to that," she said, her face very white. She placed her hand to her breast and said: "By the way, you've hurt me."

He replied: "I'm sorry if I hurt you. I didn't intend to. I simply wanted to get the letter, that's all."

"All right," she answered. "I'll excuse you for hurting me."

Then the waitress entered with the sweet and their conversation was abruptly interrupted.

After dinner he went back into the lounge and took up an illustrated paper Somehow, he did not feel inclined to try to rewrite the letter to Clare. And in any case, he could not have remembered more than bits of it; it would have to be a fresh letter if he wrote at all.

Helen came downstairs to him with hat and coat on ready for outdoors.

"Good-bye," she said, "I'm going."

He said: "Hadn't I better take you down to the place? I don't mind a bit of a walk, you know."

She answered: "Oh, no, don't bother. It's not far. You get on with your letter-writing."

Then she paused almost at the door of the lounge, and said, coming back to him suddenly: "Kiss me before I go, Kenneth."

He kissed her. Then she smiled and went out.

An hour later he started another letter to Clare.

"MY DEAR, dear CLARE,—I'm so pleased it has not all come to an end! ... All those hours we spent together, all the work we have shared, all our joy and laughter and sympathy together—it could not have counted for nothing, could it? We dare not have put an end to it; we should fear being haunted all our lives. We ..."

Then the tired feeling came on him, and he no longer wanted to write, not even to Clare. He put the hardly-begun letter in his pocket —carefully, this time—and took up the illustrated paper again. He half wished he had gone with Helen to the kinema.... A quarter to ten.... It would soon be time for him to stroll out and meet her.

Walking along the promenade to the beach kinema he solemnly reviewed his life. He saw kaleidoscopically his childhood days at Beachings Over, then the interludes at Harrow and Cambridge, and then the sudden tremendous plunge—Millstead! It seemed to him that ever since that glowering April afternoon when he had first stepped into Ervine's dark study, events had been shaping themselves relentlessly to his ruin. He could see himself as a mere automaton, moved upon by the calm accurate fingers of fate. His meeting with Helen, his love of her and hers for him, their marriage, their slow infinitely wearisome estrangement—all seemed as if it had been planned with sinister deliberation. Only one section of his life had been dominated by his own free will, and that was the part of it that had to do with Clare. He pondered over the subtle differentiation, and decided at last that it was invalid, and that fate had operated at least as much with Clare as with Helen. And yet, for all that, the distinction remained in his mind. His life with Helen seemed to press him down, to cramp him in a narrow groove, to deprive him of all self-determination; it was only when he came to Clare that he was free again and could do as he liked. Surely it was he himself, and not fate, that drew him joyously to Clare.

The mist that had hovered over Seacliffe all day was now magically lifted, and out of a clear sky there shone a moon with the slightest of yellow haloes encircling it. The promenade was nearly deserted, and in all the tall cliff of boarding-houses along the Marine Parade there was hardly a window with a light in it. The solitary redness of the lamp on the end of the pier sent a soft shimmer over the intervening water; the sea, at almost high tide, was quite calm. Hardly a murmur of the waves reached his ears as he strolled briskly along, but that was because they were right up against the stone wall of the promenade and had no beach of pebbles to be noisy with.

He leaned over the railings and saw the water immediately beneath him, silvered in moonlight. Seacliffe was beautiful now.... Then he looked ahead and saw the garish illuminations of the solitary picturepalace that Seacliffe possessed, and he wondered how Helen or anybody could prefer a kinema entertainment to the glory of the night outside. And yet, he reflected, the glory of the night was a subjective business; it required a certain mood; whereas the kinema created its own mood, asking and requiring nothing. Poor Helen!

Why should pity for her have overwhelmed him suddenly at that moment? He did not love her, not the least fraction; yet he would have died for her if such had need to be. If she were in danger he would not stay to think; he would risk life or limb for her sake without a premonitory thought. He almost longed for the opportunity to sacrifice himself for her in some such way. He felt he owed it to her. But there was one sacrifice that was too hard—he could not live with her in contentment, giving up Clare. He knew he couldn't. He saw quite clearly in the future the day when he would leave Helen and go to Clare. Not fate this time, but the hungering desire of his heart, that would not let him rest.

And yet, was not this same desire fate itself, his own fate, leading him on and further to some inevitable end? Only that he did not fear it. He opened wide his arms, welcoming it, longing for and therefore unconscious of its domination.

He stood in front of the gilded dinginess of the picture-place, pondering on his destiny, when there came up to him a shabby little man in a long tattered overcoat, who asked him for a light. Speed, who was so anxious not to be a snob that he usually gave to strangers the impression of being one, proffered a box of matches and smiled. But for the life of him he could not think of anything to say He felt he ought to say something, lest the other fellow might think him surly; he racked his brain for some appropriate remark and eventually said: "Nice night." The other lit the stump of a cigarette contemplatively and replied: "Yes. Nice night.... Thanks.... Waiting for somebody?"

"Yes," replied Speed, rather curtly He had no desire to continue the conversation, still less to discuss his own affairs.

"Rotten hole, Seacliffe, in winter," resumed the stranger, showing no sign of moving on.

"Yes," agreed Speed.

"Nothing to do—nowhere to go—absolutely the deadest place on God's earth. I live here and I know Every night I take a stroll about this time and to-night's bin the first night this year I've ever seen anything happen at all."

"Indeed?"

The stranger ignored the obvious boredness of Speed's voice, and continued: "Yes. That's the truth. But it happened all right tonight. Quite exciting, in fact."

He looked at Speed to see if his interest was in any way aroused. Such being not yet so he remarked again: "Yes, quite exciting." He paused and added:

"Bit gruesome perhaps—to some folks."

Speed said, forcing himself to be interested:

"Why, what was it?"

And the other, triumphant that he had secured an attentive audience at last, replied: "Body found. Pulled up off the breakwater.... Drowned, of course."

Even now Speed was only casually interested.

"Really? And who was it?"

"Don't know the name.... A woman's body."

"Nobody identified her yet?"

"Not yet. They say she's not a Seacliffe woman.... See there!" He pointed back along the promenade towards a spot where, not half an hour ago, Speed had leaned over the railings to see the moonlight on the sea. "Can you see the crowd standing about? That's where

they dragged her in. Only about ten minutes ago as I was passin'. Very high tide, you know, washes all sorts of things up.... I didn't stay long—bit too gruesome for me."

"Yes," agreed Speed. "And for me too.... By the way d'you happen to know when this picture house shuts up?"

"About half-past ten, mostly."

"Thanks."

"Well—I'll be gettin' along.... Much obliged for the light.... Goodnight...."

"Good-night," said Speed.

A few minutes later the crowd began to tumble out of the kinema. He stood in the darkness against a blank wall, where he could see without being seen. He wondered whether he had not better take Helen home through the town instead of along the promenade. It was a longer way, of course, but it would avoid the unpleasant affair that the stranger had mentioned to him. He neither wished to see himself nor wished Helen to see anything of the sort.

Curious that she was so late? The kinema must be almost empty now; the stream of people had stopped. He saw the manager going to the box-office to lock up. "Have they all come out?" he asked, emerging into the rays of the electric lights. "Yes, everybody," answered the other. He even glanced at Speed suspiciously, as if he wondered why he should be waiting for somebody who obviously hadn't been to the kinema at all.

Well.... Speed stood in a sheltered alcove and lit a cigarette. He had better get back to the Beach Hotel, anyway. Perhaps Helen hadn't gone to the picture-show after all. Or, perhaps, she had come out before the end and they had missed each other. Perhaps anything.... Anything! ...

Then suddenly the awful thought occurred to him. At first it was fantastic; he walked along, sampling it in a horrified fashion, yet refusing to be in the least perturbed by it. Then it gained ground upon him, made him hasten his steps, throw away his cigarette, and

finally run madly along the echoing promenade to the curious little silent crowd that had gathered there, about half-way to the pier entrance. He scampered along the smooth asphalt just like a boisterous youngster, yet in his eyes was wild brain-maddening fear.

VTen minutes later he knew. They pointed to a gap in the railings close by, made some while before by a lorry that had run out of control along the Marine Parade. The Urban District Council ought to have repaired the railings immediately after the accident, and he (somebody in the crowd) would not be surprised if the coroner censured the Council pretty severely at the inquest. The gap was a positive death-trap for anybody walking along at night and not looking carefully ahead. And he (somebody else in the crowd) suggested the possibility of making the Seacliffe Urban District Council pay heavy damages.... Of course, it was an accident.... There was a bad bruise on the head: that was where she must have struck the stones as she fell.... And in one of the pockets was a torn kinema ticket; clearly she had been on her way home from the Beach kinema.... Once again, it was the Council's fault for not promptly repairing the dangerous gap in the railings.

They led him back to the Beach Hotel and gave him brandy He kept saying: "Now please go—I'm quite all right.... There's really nothing that anybody can do for me.... Please go now...."

When at last he was alone in the cheerless hotel bedroom he sat down on the side of the bed and cried. Not for sorrow or pity or terror, but merely to relieve some fearful strain of emotion that was in him. Helen dead! He could hardly force himself to believe it, but when he did he felt sorry, achingly sorry, because there had been so many bonds between them, so many bonds that only death could have snapped. He saw her now, poor little woman, as he had never

seen her before; the love in her still living, and all that had made them unhappy together vanished away. He loved her, those minutes in the empty, cheerless bedroom, more calmly than he had ever loved her when she had been near to him. And—strange miracle!— she had given him peace at last. Pity for her no longer overwhelmed him with its sickly torture; he was calm, calm with sorrow, but calm.

VI

Then, slowly, grimly, as to some fixed and inevitable thing, his torture returned. He tried to persuade himself that the worst was over, that tragedy had spent its terrible utmost; but even the sad calm of desperation was nowhere to be found. He paced up and down the bedroom long and wearisomely; shortly after midnight the solitary gas-jet faltered and flickered and finally abandoned itself with a forlorn pop. "Curse the place!" he muttered, acutely nervous in the sudden gloom; then for some moments he meditated a sarcastic protest to the hotel-proprietress in the morning. "I am aware," he would begin, tartly, "that the attractions of Seacliffe in the evenings are not such as would often tempt the visitor to keep up until the small hours; but don't you think that is an argument against rather than for turning off the gas-supply at midnight?" Rather ponderous, though; probably the woman wouldn't know what he meant. He might write a letter to the Seacliffe Gazette about it, anyway. "Oh, damn them!" he exclaimed, with sudden fervour, as he searched for the candle on the dressing-table. Unfortunately he possessed no matches, and the candlestick, when at last his groping had discovered it, contained none, either. It was so infernally dark and silent; everybody in the place was in bed except himself. He pictured the maids, sleeping cosily in the top attics, or perhaps chattering together in whispers about clothes or their love-affairs or Seacliffe gossip or—why, of course!—about him. They would surely be talking about him. Such a tit-bit of gossip! Everyone in Seacliffe would be

full of the tragedy of the young fellow whose wife, less than a year married, had fallen accidentally into the sea off the promenade! He, not she, would be the figure of high tragedy in their minds, and on the morrow they would all stare at him morbidly, curiously.... Good God in Heaven! Could he endure it? ... Lightly the moonlight filtered through the Venetian blinds on to the garish linoleum pattern; and when the blinds were stirred by the breeze the light skipped along the floor like moving swords; he could not endure that, anyway. He went to the windows and drew up the blinds, one after the other. They would hear that, he reflected, if they were awake; they would know he was not asleep.

Then he remembered her as he had seen her less than a twelvemonth before; standing knee-deep in the grasses by the riverbank at Parminters. Everywhere that he had loved her was so clear now in his mind, and everywhere else was so unreal and dim. He heard the tinkle of the Head's piano and saw her puzzling intently over some easy Chopin mazurka, her golden hair flame-like in the sunlight of the afternoon. He saw the paths and fields of Millstead, all radiant where she and he had been, and the moonlight lapping the pavilion steps, where, first of all, he had touched her lips with his. And then—only with an effort could he picture this—he saw the grim room downstairs, where she lay all wet and bedraggled, those cheeks that he had kissed ice-cold and salt with the sea. The moon, emerging fully from behind a mist, plunged him suddenly in white light; at that moment it seemed to him that he was living in some ugly nightmare, and that shortly he would wake from it and find all the tragedy untrue. Helen was alive and well: he could only have imagined her dead. And downstairs, in that sitting-room—it had been no more than a dream, fearful and—thank God—false. Helen was away, somewhere, perfectly well and happy—somewhere. And downstairs, in that sitting-room ... Anyhow, he would go down and see, to convince himself. He unlocked the bedroom door and tiptoed out on to the landing. He saw the moon's rays caught phosphorescently on a fish in a glass case. Down the two flights of stairs he descended with caution, and then, at the foot, strove to recollect which was the room. He saw two doors, with something written on them. One was the bar-parlour, he thought, where the

worthies of Seacliffe congregated nightly He turned the handle and saw the glistening brass of the beer-engines. Then the other door, might be? He tried the handle, but the door was locked. Somehow this infuriated him. "They lock the doors and turn off the gas!" he cried, vehemently, uniting his complaints. Then suddenly he caught sight of another door in the wall opposite, a door on which there was no writing at all. He had an instant conviction that this must be the door. He strode to it, menacingly, took hold of its handle in a firm grasp, and pushed. Locked again! This time he could not endure the fury that raged within him. "Good God!" he cried, shouting at the top of his voice, "I'll burst every door in the place in!" He beat on the panels with his fists, shouting and screaming the whole while....

Ten minutes later the hotel-porter and the bar man, clad in trousers and shirt only, were holding his arms on either side, and the proprietress, swathed in a pink dressing-gown, was standing a little way off, staring at him curiously. And he was complaining to her about the turning off of the gas at midnight. "One really has a right to expect something more generous from the best hotel in Seacliffe," he was saying, with an argumentative mildness that surprised himself. "It is not as though this were a sixpenny doss-house. It is an A.A. listed hotel, and I consider it absolutely scandalous that ..."

VII

Strangely, when he was back again and alone in his own bedroom, he felt different. His gas-jet was burning again, evidently as a result of his protest; the victory gave him a curious, childish pleasure. Nor did his burdens weigh so heavily on him; indeed, he felt even peaceful enough to try to sleep. He undressed and got into bed.

And then, slowly, secretly, dreadfully, he discovered that he was thinking about Clare! It frightened him—this way she crept into his

thoughts as pain comes after the numbness of a blow He knew he ought not to think of her. He ought to put her out of his mind, at any rate, for the present. Helen dead this little while, and already Clare in his thoughts! The realisation appalled him, terrified him by affording him a glimpse into the depths of his own dark soul. And yet—he could not help it. Was he to be blamed for the thoughts that he could not drive out of his mind? He prayed urgently and passionately for sleep, that he might rid himself of the lurking, lurking image of her. But even in sleep he feared he might dream of her.

Oh, Clare, Clare, would she ever come to him now, now that he was alone and Helen was dead? God, the awfulness of the question! Yet he could not put it away from him; he could but deceive himself, might be, into thinking he was not asking it. He wanted Clare. Not more than ever—only as much as he had always wanted her.

He wondered solemnly if the stuff in him were rotten; if he were proven vile and debased because he wanted her; if he were cancelling his soul by thinking of her so soon. And yet—God help him; even if all that were so, he could not help it. If he were to be damned eternally for thinking about Clare, then let him be damned eternally. Actions he might control, but never the strains and cravings of his own mind. If he were wrong, therefore, let him be wrong.

He wondered whether, when he fell asleep, he would dream about Helen or about Clare. And yet, when at last his very tiredness made him close his eyes, he dreamed of neither of them, but slept in perfect calm, as a child that has been forgiven.

In the morning they brought his breakfast up to him in bed, and with it a letter and a telegram. The chambermaid asked him dubiously if he were feeling better and he replied: "Oh yes, much better, thanks." Only vaguely could he remember what had taken place during the night.

When the girl had gone and he had glanced at the handwriting on the envelope, he had a sudden paralysing shock, for it was Helen's!

The postmark was: "Seacliffe, 10.10 p.m."

He tore open the envelope with slow and awful dread, and took out a single sheet of Beach Hotel notepaper. Scribbled on it in pencil was just:

"DEAR KENNETH" ("Dear" underlined),—Good-bye, darling. I can't bear you not to be happy. Forget me and don't worry. They will think it has been an accident, and you mustn't tell them anything else. Leave Millstead and take Clare away. Be happy with her.—Yours, HELEN."—

"P.S.—There's one thing I'm sorry for. On the last night before we left Millstead I said something about Clare and Pritchard. Darling, it was a lie—I made it up because I couldn't bear you to love Clare so much. I don't mind now. Forgive me."

A moment later he was opening the telegram and reading: "Shall arrive Seacliffe Station one fifteen meet me Clare."

It had been despatched from Millstead at nine-five that morning, evidently as soon as the post office opened.

He ate no breakfast. It was a quarter past eleven and the sun was streaming in through the window—the first spring day of the year. He re-read the letter.

Strange that until then the thought that the catastrophe could have been anything at all but accidental had never even remotely occurred to him! Now it came as a terrible revelation, hardly to be believed, even with proof; a revelation of that utmost misery that had driven her to the sea. He had known that she was not happy, but he had never guessed that she might be miserable to death.

And what escape was there now from his own overwhelming guilt? She had killed herself because he had not made her happy. Or else because she had not been able to make him happy. Whichever it was, he was fearfully to blame. She had killed herself to make room for that other woman who had taken all the joy out of her life.

And at one-fifteen that other woman would arrive in Seacliffe.

In the darkest depths of his remorse he vowed that he would not meet her, see her, or hold any communication with her ever again, so long as his life lasted. He would hate her eternally, for Helen's sake. He would dedicate his life to the annihilation of her in his mind. Why was she coming? Did she know? How could she know? He raved at her mentally, trying to involve her in some share of his own deep treachery, for even the companionship of guilt was at least companionship. The two of them—Clare and himself—had murdered Helen. The two of them—together. Together. There was black magic in the intimacy that that word implied—magic in the guilty secret that was between them, in the passionate iniquity that was alluring even in its baseness!

He dressed hurriedly, and with his mind in a ferment, forgot his breakfast till it was cold and then found it too unpalatable to eat. As he descended the stairs and came into the hotel lobby he remarked to the proprietress: "Oh, by the way, I must apologise for making a row last night. Fact is, my nerves, you know.... Rather upset...."

"Quite all right, Mr. Speed. I'm sure we all understand and sympathise with you. If there's any way we can help you, you know.... Shall you be in to lunch?"

"Lunch? Oh yes—er—I mean, no. No, I don't think I shall—not today. You see there are—er—arrangements to make—er— arrangements, you know ..."

He smiled, and with carefully simulated nonchalance, commenced to light a cigarette! When he got outside the hotel he decided that it was absolutely the wrong thing to have done. He flung the cigarette into the gutter. What was the matter with him? Something,— something that made him, out of very fear, do ridiculous and inappropriate things. The same instinct, no doubt, that always made him talk loudly when he was nervous. And then he remembered that April morning of the year before, when he had first of all entered the Headmaster's study at Millstead; for then, through nervousness, he had spoken loudly, almost aggressively, to disguise his embarrassment. What a curious creature he was, and how curious people must think him.

He strolled round the town, bought a morning paper at the news agent's, and pretended to be interested in the contents. Over him like a sultry shadow lay the disagreeable paraphernalia of the immediate future: doctors, coroner, inquest, lawyers, interviews with Doctor and Mrs. Ervine, and so on. It had all to be gone through, but for the present he would try to forget it. The turmoil of his own mind, that battle which was being waged within his inmost self, that strife which no coroner would guess, those secrets which no inquest would or could elicit; these were the things of greater import. In the High Street, leading up from the Pierhead, he saw half a dozen stalwart navvies swinging sledge-hammers into the concrete roadbed. He stopped, ostensibly to wait for a tram, but really to watch them. He envied them, passionately; envied their strength and animal simplicity; envied above all their lack of education and ignorance of themselves, their happy blindness along the path of life. He wished he could forget such things as Art and Culture and Education, and could become as they, or as he imagined them to be. Their lives were brimful of real things, things to be held and touched —hammers and levers and slabs of concrete. With all their crude joy and all their pain, simple and physical, their souls grew strong and stark. He envied them with a passion that made him desist at last from the sight of them, because it hurt.

The town-hall clock began the hour of noon, and that reminded him of Clare, and of the overwhelming fact that she was at that moment in the train hastening to Seacliffe. Was he thinking of her again? He went into a café and ordered in desperation a pot of China tea and some bread and butter, as if the mere routine of a meal would rid his mind of her. For desire was with him still, nor could he stave it off. Nothing that he could ever discover, however ugly or terrible, could stop the craving of him for Clare. The things that they had begun together, he and she, had no ending in this world. And suddenly all sense of free-will left him, and he felt himself propelled at a mighty rate towards her, wherever she might be; fate, surely, guiding him to her, but this time, a fate that was urging him from within, not pressing him from without. And he knew, secretly, whatever indignant protests he might make to himself about it, that

when the 1:15 train entered Seacliffe station he would be waiting there on the platform for her. The thing was inevitable, like death.

But inevitability did not spare him torment. And at last his remorse insisted upon a compromise. He would meet Clare, he decided, but when he had met her, he would proceed to torture her, subtly, shrewdly—seeking vengeance for the tragedy that she had brought to his life, and the spell that she had cast upon his soul. He would be the Grand Inquisitor.

He was very white and haggard when the time came. He had reached the station as early as one o'clock, and for a quarter of an hour had lounged about the deserted platforms. Meanwhile the sun shone gloriously, and the train as it ran into the station caught the sunlight on its windows. The sight of the long line of coaches, curving into the station like a flaming sword into its scabbard, gave him a mighty heart-rending thrill. Yes, yes—he would torture her.... His eyes glinted with diabolical exhilaration, and a touch of hectic colour crept into his wan cheeks. He watched her alight from a thirdclass compartment near the rear of the train. Then he lost her momentarily amidst the emptying crowd. He walked briskly against the stream of the throng, with a heart that beat fast with unutterable expectations.

But how he loved her as he saw her coming towards him!— though he tried with all his might to kindle hate in his heart. She smiled and held out her tiny hand. He took it with a limpness that was to begin his torture of her. She was to notice that limpness.

"How is Helen?" was her first remark.

Amidst the bustle of the luggage round the guard's van he replied quietly: "Helen? Oh, she's all right. I didn't tell her you were coming."

"You were wise," she answered.

A faint thrill of anticipation crept over him; this diabolical game was interesting, fascinating, in its way; and would lead her very securely into a number of traps. And why, he thought, did she think it was wise of him not to have told Helen?

In the station-yard she suddenly stopped to consult a time-table hoarding.

"What are you doing?" he asked.

"I'm looking for the next train back to Millstead."

"Not the next, surely?"

"Why not? What do you think I've come for?"

"I don't know in the least. What have you come for?"

She looked at him appealingly. He saw, with keen and instant relish, that she had already noticed something of hostility in his attitude towards her. The torture had begun. For the first time, she was subject to his power and not he to hers.

"I've come for a few minutes' conversation," she answered, quietly. "And the next train back is at 3:18."

"You mean to travel by that?"

"Yes."

"Then we needn't stay in the station till then, need we? Let's walk somewhere. We've two whole hours—time enough to get right out of the town and back again. I hate conversations in railway-stations."

But his chief reason was a desire to secure the right scenic background for his torture of her.

"All right," she answered, and looked at him again appealingly. The tears almost welled into his own eyes because of the deep sadness that was in hers. How quick she was to feel his harshness! —he thought. How marvellously sensitive was that little soul of hers to the subtlest gradations of his own mood! What fiendish torture he could put her to, by no more, might be, than the merest upraising of an eyebrow, the faintest change of the voice, the slightest tightening of the lips! She was of mercury, like himself; responsive to every touch of the emotional atmosphere. And was not that the reason why she understood him with such wonderful instinctive intimacy,—was not that the reason why the two of them, out of the whole world, would have sought each other like twin magnets?

He led her, in silence, through the litter of mean streets near the station, and thence, beyond the edge of the town, towards the meadows that sloped to the sea. So far it had been a perfect day, but now the sun was half-quenching itself in a fringe of mist that lay along the horizon; and with the change there came a sudden pink light that lit both their faces and shone behind them on the tawdry newness of the town, giving it for once a touch of pitiful loveliness. He took her into a rolling meadow that tapered down into a coppice, and as they reached the trees the last shaft of sunlight died from the sky Then they plunged into the grey depths, with all the freshlybudded leaves brushing against their faces, and the very earth, so it seemed, murmuring at their approach. Already there was the hint of rain in the air.

"It's a long way to come for a few minutes' conversation," he began.

She answered, ignoring his remark: "I had a letter from Helen this morning."

"What!" he exclaimed in sharp fear. He went suddenly white.

"A letter," she went on, broodingly. "Would you like to see it?"

He stared at her and replied: "I would rather hear from you what it was about."

He saw her brown eyes looking up curiously into his, and he had the instant feeling that she would cry if he persisted in his torture of her. The silence of that walk from the station had unnerved her, had made her frightened of him. That was what he had intended. And she did not know yet—did not know what he knew. Poor girl—what a blow was in waiting for her! But he must not let it fall for a little while.

She bit her lip and said: "Very well. It was about you. She was unhappy about you. Dreadfully unhappy. She said she was going to leave you. She also said—that she was going to leave you—to—to me."

Her voice trembled on that final word. "Well?"

She recovered herself to continue with more energy: "And I've come here to tell you this—that if she does leave you, I shan't have you. That's all."

"You are making large assumptions."

"I know. And I don't mind your sarcasm, though I don't think any more of you for using it.... I repeat what I said—if Helen leaves you or if you leave Helen, I shall have nothing more to do with you."

"It is certainly kind of you to warn me in time."

"You've never given Helen a fair trial. I know you and she are illmatched. I know you oughtn't to have married her at all, but that doesn't matter—you've done it, and you've got to be fair to her. And if you think that because I've confessed that I love you I'm in your power for you to be cruel to, you're mistaken!" Her voice rose passionately

He stared at her, admiring the warm flush that came into her cheeks, and all the time pitying her, loving her, agonisingly!

"Understand," she went on, "You've got to look after Helen— you've got to take care of her—watch her—do you know what I mean?"

"No. What do you mean?"

"I mean you must try to make her happy. She's sick and miserable, and, somehow, you must cure her I came here to see you because I thought I could persuade you to be kind to her. I thought if you loved me at all, you might do it for my sake. Remember I love Helen as well as you. Do you still think I'm hardhearted and cold? If you knew what goes on inside me, the racking, raging longing—the— No, no—what's the good of talking of that to you? You either understand or else you don't, and if you don't, no words of mine will make you.... But I warn you again, you must cure Helen of her unhappiness. Otherwise, she might try to cure herself— in any way, drastic or not, that occurred to her. Do you know now what I mean?"

"I'm afraid I don't, even yet."

Turn static files into dynamic content formats.

Create a flipbook
Issuu converts static files into: digital portfolios, online yearbooks, online catalogs, digital photo albums and more. Sign up and create your flipbook.