defining conservatism

Page 1

1 W. D. S. Pennington Outline for a Definition of Conservatism 03.00.21 Today, the routing of classical conservatism is rampant—yet its essential promise remains unconquered. Starved of an intellectual center, of a focal point for thoughtful deliberation, classical conservatism is confused, unsure, self-condemned to cycles of debasement. Conservatism does not know itself, it cannot speak for itself, does not recognize its own oncefamiliar, once-principled motivations. It lacks confidence; it lacks creativity; it lacks definition. The following is an attempt to designate such a definition. Insofar as we lack a robust definition and working understanding of conservatism’s true identity, so too does our capacity to exist as time-bound creatures in this world diminish; we become less, the depth of our being made shallow. Without a proper conservative discourse, we do not know how to say “yes” or “no” to time; we do not know how to award permanence or avoid decay, when to wait and when to intervene, how to judge, decide or choose. Conservatism’s promise rests in its capacity to respond to this existential deficit. Conservatism is: the deliberate use of human choice to challenge the arrogance of time. It is to use time, to use experience, in the service of human community; to arrest rather than resist, to pull from the everflow the most essential, the most human, the most home-building technologies of politicking and world-building yet developed. The exaltation of choice and decision is here paramount, and prudence becomes the conservative battle-standard. This prudence is informed by history, and seeks to either “yes-say” or “no-say” toward the time-bound conditions from which it springs: prescription of custom, the accumulated knowledge-bank of history, is central to the exercise of prudence, and is seen as local, contingent and historical. To this end, elements of classical conservatism dovetail with theoretical pragmatism, insofar as both are concerned and begin with the reality of organisms in their actual ecosystems, with the prioritization of the empirical assessment of the “facts on the ground,” on with the rejection of monistic abstractions and a focus on the real, rooted, embodied interests involved. Both systems of thought are fundamentally “bottom-up” pluralistic philosophies that promote human growth, development and flourishing—different in the details, but bound in a similar rejection of the ultimate “perfectibility” of man and the positive liberties that so often manifest in violent fascisms and all-devouring totalitarianisms. Contingency, adaptability, novelty: the great ebb and flow of raw experience is both the moral and political concern of classical conservatism. Below, I outline the five key philosophical commitments of an updated establishment conservatism. Taken individually, these principles are not unique to conservatism: as mentioned, the focus on experience and plurality conservatism shares with philosophical pragmatism; with liberalism, including the Lockean variant, it shares the idea that politics is a secondary phenomenon responding to primary human needs and desires; the analysis of the dynamic interactions between agent and environment links conservatism to strands of Hegelianism and even, at its limit-break, Marxism; and the relationship between freedom and homeness recalls


Turn static files into dynamic content formats.

Create a flipbook
Issuu converts static files into: digital portfolios, online yearbooks, online catalogs, digital photo albums and more. Sign up and create your flipbook.